July 1, 2024
DU LLBLabour LawSemester 4

Bangalore Water Supply & Sewerage Board v. A. RajappaAIR 1978 SC 548

Case Summary

Citation
Keywords
Facts
Issues
Contentions
Law Points
Judgement
Ratio Decidendi & Case Authority

Full Case Details

V.R. KRISHNA IYER, J. – 25. The rather zigzag course of the landmark cases and the
tangled web of judicial thought have perplexed one branch of Industrial Law, resulting from
obfuscation of the basic concept of ‘industry’ under the Industrial Disputes Act, 1947 (for
short, the Act). This bizarre situation, 30 years after the Act was passed and industrialisation
had advanced on a national scale, could not be allowed to continue longer. So, the urgent need
for an authoritative resolution of this confused position which has survived – indeed, has been
accentuated by – the judgment of the six-member Bench in Safdarjung (Management of
Safdar Jang Hospital, New Delhi v. Kuldip Singh Sethi [AIR 1970 SC 1407)] if we may
say so with deep respect, has led to a reference to a larger Bench of this die-hard dispute as to
what an ‘industry’ under Section 2(j) means.

  1. Legalese and logomachy have the genius to inject mystique into common words,
    alienating the laity in effect from the rule of law. What is the common worker or ordinary
    employer to do if he is bewildered by a definitional dilemma and is unsure whether his
    enterprise, say, a hospital, a university, a library, a service club, a local body, a research
    institute, a pinjarapole, a chamber of commerce, a Gandhi Ashram, is an industry at all?
  2. Back to the single problem of thorny simplicity: what is an ‘industry’? Historically
    speaking, this Indian statute has its beginnings in Australia, even as the bulk of our corpus
    juris, with a colonial flavour, is a carbon copy of English law. Therefore, in interpretation, we
    may seek light Australasially, and so it is that the precedents of this Court have drawn on
    Australian cases as on English dictionaries. But India is India and its individuality, in law and
    society, is attested by its National Charter, so that statutory construction must be home-spun
    even if hospitable to alien thinking.
  3. The reference to us runs thus:
    One should have thought that an activist Parliament by taking quick policy
    decisions and by resorting to amendatory processes would have simplified, clarified
    and de-limited the definition of “industry”, and, if we may add “workman”. Had this
    been done with aware and alert speed by the Legislature, litigation which is the
    besetting sin of industrial life could well have been avoided by a considerable degree.
    That consummation may perhaps happen on a distant day, but this Court has to
    decide from day to day disputes involving this branch of industrial law and give
    guidance by declaring what is an industry, through the process of interpretation and
    re-interpretation, with a murky accumulation of case-law. Counsels on both sides
    have chosen to rely on Safdarjung each emphasising one part or other of the decision
    39
    as supporting his argument. Rulings of this Court before and after have revealed no
    unanimity nor struck any unison and so, we confess to an inability to discern any
    golden thread running through the string of decisions bearing on the issue at hand.
    (T)he chance of confusion from the crop of cases in an area where the common
    man has to understand and apply the law makes it desirable that there should be a
    comprehensive, clear and conclusive declaration as to what is an industry under the
    Industrial Disputes Act as it now stands. Therefore, we think it necessary to place this
    case before the learned Chief Justice for consideration by a larger Bench. If in the
    meantime the Parliament does not act, this Court may have to illumine the twilight
    area of law and help the industrial community carry on smoothly.
  4. So, the long and short of it is what is an industry? Section 2(j) defines it:
    “industry” means any business, trade, undertaking, manufacture or calling of
    employers and includes any calling, service, employment, handicraft, or industrial
    occupation or avocation of workmen.
    Let us put it plain. The canons of construction are trite that we must read the statute as a
    whole to get a hang of it and a holistic perspective of it. We must have regard to the historical
    background, objects and reasons, international thoughtways, popular understanding,
    contextual connotation and suggestive subject-matter. Equally important, dictionaries, while
    not absolutely binding, are aids to ascertain meaning. Nor are we writing on a tabula rasa.
    Since Banerji (D.N. Banerji v. P.R. Mukherjee [AIR 1953 SC 58], decided a silver jubilee
    span of years ago, we have a heavy harvest of rulings on what is an ‘industry’ and we have to
    be guided by the variorum of criteria stated therein, as far as possible, and not spring a
    creative surprise on the industrial community by a stroke of freak originality.
  5. A look at the definition, dictionary in hand, decisions in head and Constitution at
    heart, leads to some sure characteristics of an ‘industry’, narrowing down the twilit zone of
    turbid controversy. An industry is a continuity, is an organized activity, is a purposeful pursuit
    — not any isolated adventure, desultory excursion or casual, fleeting engagement motivelessly
    undertaken. Such is the common feature of a trade, business, calling, manufacture –
    mechanical or handicraft-based – service, employment, industrial occupation or avocation. For
    those who know English and are not given to the luxury of splitting semantic hairs, this
    conclusion argues itself. The expression ‘undertaking’ cannot be torn off the words whose
    company it keeps. If birds of a feather flock together and noscitur a sociis is a commonsense
    guide to construction, ‘undertaking’ must be read down to conform to the restrictive
    characteristic shared by the society of words before and after. Nobody will torture
    ‘undertaking’ in Section 2(j) to mean meditation or musheira which are spiritual and aesthetic
    undertakings. Wide meanings must fall in line and discordance must be excluded from a
    sound system. From Banerji to Safdarjung and beyond, this limited criterion has passed
    muster and we see no reason, after all the marathon of argument, to shift from this position.
  6. Likewise, an ‘industry’ cannot exist without co-operative endeavour between
    employer and employee. No employer, no industry; no employee, no industry – not as a
    dogmatic proposition in economics but as an articulate major premise of the definition and the
    40
    scheme of the Act, and as a necessary postulate of industrial disputes and statutory resolution
    thereof.
  7. An industry is not a futility but geared to utilities in which the community has
    concern. And in this mundane world where law lives now, economic utilities material goods
    and services, not transcendental flights nor intangible achievements – are the functional focus
    of industry. Therefore, no temporal utilities, no statutory industry, is axiomatic. If society, in
    its advance, experiences subtler realities and assigns values to them, jurisprudence may reach
    out to such collective good. Today, not tomorrow, is the first charge of pragmatic law of
    western heritage. So we are confined to material, not ethereal end products.
  8. This much flows from a plain reading of the purpose and provision of the legislation
    and its western origin and the ratio of all the rulings. We hold these triple ingredients to be
    unexceptionable.
  9. The relevant constitutional entry speaks of industrial and labour disputes (Entry 22
    List III Schedule VII). The Preamble to the Act refers to ‘the investigation and settlement of
    industrial disputes’. The definition of industry has to be decoded in this background and our
    holding is reinforced by the fact that industrial peace, collective bargaining, strikes and lockouts, industrial adjudications, works committees of employers and employees and the like
    connote organised, systematic operations and collectively of workmen co-operating with their
    employer in producing goods and services for the community. The betterment of the
    workmen’s lot, the avoidance of outbreaks blocking production and just and speedy
    settlement of disputes concern the community. In trade and business, goods and services are
    for the community, not for self-consumption.
  10. The penumbral area arrives as we move on to the other essentials needed to make an
    organized, systematic activity, oriented on productive collaboration between employer and
    employee, an industry as defined in Section 2(j). Here we have to be cautious not to fall into
    the trap of definitional expansionism bordering on rcductio ad absurdum nor to truncate the
    obvious amplitude of the provision to fit it into our mental mould of beliefs and prejudices or
    social philosophy conditioned by class interests. Subjective wish shall not be father to the
    forensic thought, if credibility with a pluralist community is a value to be cherished. “Courts
    do not substitute their social and economic beliefs for the judgment of legislative bodies”.
    [See Constitution of the United States of America, Corwin, p. xxxi]. Even so, this legislation
    has something to do with social justice between the ‘haves’ and the ‘have-nots’, and naive,
    fugitive and illogical cutbacks on the import of ‘industry’ may do injustice to the benignant
    enactment. Avoiding Scylla and Charybdis we proceed to decipher the fuller import of the
    definition. To sum up, the personality of the whole statute, be it remembered, has a welfare
    basis, it being a beneficial legislation which protects labour, promotes their contentment and
    regulates situations of crisis and tension where production may be imperilled by untenable
    strikes and blackmail lock-outs. The mechanism of the Act is geared to conferment of
    regulated benefits to workmen and resolution, according to a sympathetic rule of law, of the
    conflicts, actual or potential, between management and workmen. Its goal is amelioration of
    the conditions of workers, tempered by a practical sense of peaceful co-existence, to the
    benefit of both – not a neutral position but restraints on laissez faire and concern for the
    welfare of the weaker lot. Empathy with the statute is necessary to understand not merely its
    41
    spirit, but also its sense. One of the vital concepts on which the whole statute is built, is
    ‘industry’ and when we approach the definition in Section 2(j), we must be informed by these
    values. This certainly does not mean that we should strain the language of the definition to
    import into it what we regard as desirable in an industrial legislation, for we are not
    legislating de novo but construing an existing Act. Crusading for a new type of legislation
    with dynamic ideas or humanist justice and industrial harmony cannot be under the umbrella
    of interpreting an old, imperfect enactment. Nevertheless, statutory diction speaks for today
    and tomorrow; words are semantic seeds to serve the future hour. Moreover, as earlier
    highlighted, it is legitimate to project the value-set of the Constitution, especially Part IV, in
    reading the meaning of even a pre-Constitution statute. The paramount law is paramount and
    Part IV sets out Directive Principles of State Policy which must guide the judiciary, like other
    instrumentality, in interpreting all legislation. Statutory construction is not a petrified process
    and the old bottle may, to the extent language and realism permit be filled with new wine. Of
    course, the bottle should not break or lose shape.
  11. We may start the discussion with the leading case on the point, which perhaps may be
    treated as the mariner’s compass for judicial navigation D. N. Banerji v. P. R. Mukherjee.
    But before setting sail, let us map out briefly the range of dispute around the definition.
    A definition is ordinarily the crystallisation of a legal concept promoting precision and
    rounding off blurred edges but, alas, the definition in Section 2(j), viewed in retrospect, has
    achieved the opposite. Even so, we must try to clarify. Sometimes, active interrogatories tell
    better than bland affirmatives and so marginal omissions notwithstanding, we will string the
    points together in a few questions on which we have been addressed.
  12. A cynical jurist surveying the forensic scene may make unhappy comments. Counsel
    for the respondent Unions sounded that note. A pluralist society with a capitalist backbone,
    notwithstanding the innocuous adjective ‘socialist’ added to the Republic by the Constitution
    (Forty-second Amendment Act, 1976) regards profit-making as a sacrosanct value. Elitist
    professionalism and industrialism is sensitive to the ‘worker’ menace and inclines to exclude
    such sound and fury as ‘labour unrest from its sanctified precincts by judicially deindustrialising the activities of professional men and interest groups to the extent feasible.
    Governments, in a mixed economy, share some of the habits of thought of the dominant class
    and doctrines like sovereign functions, which pull out economic enterprises run by them,
    come in handy. The latent love for club life and charitable devices and escapist institutions
    bred by clever capitalism and hierarchical social structure, shows up as inhibitions transmuted
    as doctrines, interpretatively carving out immunities from the ‘industrial’ demands of labour
    by labelling many enterprises ‘non-industries’. Universities, clubs, institutes, manufactories
    and establishments managed by eleemosynary or holy entities, are instances. To objectify
    doctrinally subjective consternation is casuistry.
  13. A counter-critic on the other hand, may acidly contend that if judicial interpretation,
    uninformed by life’s realities, were to go wild, every home will be, not a quiet castle but
    tumultuous industry, every research unit will grind to a halt, every god will face new
    demands, every service club will be the venue of rumble and every charity choked off by
    brewing unrest and the salt of the earth as well as the lowliest and the lost will suffer. Counsel
    for the appellants struck this pessimistic note. Is it not obvious from these rival thoughtways
    42
    that law is value-loaded, that social philosophy is an inarticulate interpretative tool? This is
    inescapable in any school of jurisprudence.
  14. Now let us itemise, illustratively, the posers springing from the competing
    submissions, so that the contentions may be concretised.
    (1) (a) Are establishments, run without profit motive, industries?
    (b) Are charitable institutions industries?
    (c) Do undertakings governed by a no-profit-no-loss rule, statutorily or
    otherwise fastened, fall within the definition in Section 2(j)
    (d) Do clubs or other organisations (like the Y. M. C. A.) whose general
    emphasis is not on profit-making but fellowship and self-service, fit into the definitional
    circle?
    (e) To go to the core of the matter, is it an inalienable ingredient of ‘industry’
    that it should be plied with a commercial object?
    (2) (a) Should co-operation between employer and employee be direct in so far as
    it relates to the basic service or essential manufacture which is the output of the
    undertaking?
    (b) Could a lawyer’s chambers or chartered accountant’s office, a doctor’s
    clinic or other liberal profession’s occupation or calling be designated an industry?
    (c) Would a university or college or school or research institute be called an
    industry?
    (3) (a) Is the inclusive part of the definition in Section 2(j) relevant to the
    determination of an industry? If so, what impact does it make on the categories?
    (b) Do domestic service drudges who slave without respite — become
    ‘industries’ by this extended sense?
    (4) Are governmental functions, stricto sensu, industrial and if not, what is the extent
    of the immunity of instrumentalities of government?
    (5) What rational criterion exists for a cut-back on the dynamic potential and
    semantic sweep of the definition, implicit in the industrial law of a progressive society
    geared to greater industrialisation and consequent concern for regulating relations and
    investigating disputes between employers and employees as industrial processes and
    relations become more complex and sophisticated and workmen become more lightconscious?
    (6) As the provision now stands, is it scientific to define ‘industry’ based on the
    nature – the dominant nature – of the activity, i.e. on the terms of the work, remuneration
    and conditions of service which bond the two wings together into an employer-employee
    complex?
  15. Back to Banerji, to begin at the very beginning. Technically, this Bench that hears the
    appeals now is not bound by any of the earlier decisions. But we cannot agree with Justice
    Roberts of the U. S. Supreme Court that ‘adjudications of the Court were rapidly gravitating
    43
    into the same class as a restricted railroad ticket, good for this day and train only’ (See
    Corwin XVII). The present – even the revolutionary present – does not break wholly with the
    past but breaks bread with it, without being swallowed by it and may eventually swallow it.
    While it is true, academically speaking, that the Court should be ultimately right rather than
    consistently wrong, the social interest in the certainty of the law is a value which urges
    continuity where possible, clarification where sufficient and correction where derailment,
    misdirection or fundamental flaw defeats the statute or creates considerable industrial
    confusion. Shri M. K. Ramamurthy, encored by Shri R. K. Garg, argued emphatically that
    after Safdarjung, the law is in trauma and so a fresh look at the problem is ripe. The learned
    Attorney General and Shri Tarkunde, who argued at effective, illuminating length, as well as
    Dr Singhvi and Shri A. K. Sen who briefly and tellingly supplemented, did not hide the fact
    that the law is in Queer Street but sought to discern a golden thread of sound principle which
    could explain the core of the rulings which peripherally had contradictory thinking. In this
    situation, it is not wise, in our view, to reject everything ruled till date and fabricate new tests,
    aimed with lexical wisdom 01 reinforced by vintage judicial thought from Australia. Banerji
    (supra) we take as good, and, anchored on its authority, we will examine later decisions to
    stabilize the law on the firm principles gatherable therefrom, rejecting erratic excursions. To
    sip every flower and change every hour is not realism but romance which must not enchant
    the Court. Indeed, Sri Justice Chandrasekhara Aiyar, speaking for a unanimous Bench, has
    sketched the guidelines perceptively, if we may say so respectfully. Later cases have only
    added their glosses, not overruled it and the fertile source of conflict has been the bashyams
    rather than the basic decision. Therefore, our task is not to supplant the ratio of Banerji but to
    straighten and strengthen it in its application, away from different deviations and aberrations.
  16. Banerji: The Budge Budge Municipality dismissed two employees whose dispute was
    sponsored by the Union. The award of the Industrial Tribunal directed re-instatement but the
    Municipality challenged the award before the High Court and this Court on the fundamental
    ground that a municipality in discharging its normal duties connected with local selfgovernment is not engaged in any industry as defined in the Act.
  17. A panoramic view of the statute and its jurisprudentially hearings has been projected
    there and the essentials of an industry decocted. The definitions of employer [Section 2(g)],
    industry [Section 2(j)], industrial dispute [Section 2(k)], workman [Section 2(s)) are a
    statutory dictionary, not popular parlance. It is plain that merely because the employer is a
    government department or a local body (and, a fortiori, a statutory board, society or like
    entity) the enterprise does not cease to be an ‘industry’. Likewise, what the common man
    does not consider as ‘industry’ need not necessarily stand excluded from the statutory concept
    (and vice versa). The latter is deliberately drawn wider, and in some respects narrower, as
    Chandrasekhara Aiyar, J., has emphatically expressed:
    In the ordinary or non-technical sense, according to what is understood by the
    man in the street, industry or business means an undertaking where capital and labour
    co-operate with each other for the purpose of producing wealth in the shape of goods,
    machines, tools etc., and for making profits. The concept of industry in this ordinary
    sense applies even to agriculture, horticulture, pisciculture and so on and so forth. It
    is also clear that every aspect of activity in which the relationship of employer and
    44
    employee exists or arises does not thereby become an industry as commonly
    understood. We hardly think in terms of an industry, when we have regard, for
    instance, to the rights and duties of master and servant, or of a Government and its
    secretariat, or the members of the medical profession working in a hospital. It would
    be regarded as absurd to think so; at any rate the layman unacquainted with
    advancing legal concepts of what is meant by industry would rule .out such a
    connotation as impossible. There is nothing however to prevent a statute from giving
    the word “industry” and the words “industrial dispute” a wider and more
    comprehensive import in order to meet the requirements of rapid industrial progress
    and to bring about in the interests of industrial peace and economy, a fair and
    satisfactory adjustment of relations between employers and workmen in a variety of
    fields of activity. It is obvious that the limited concept of what an industry meant in
    early times must now yield place to an enormously wider concept so as to take in
    various and varied forms of industry, so that dispute arising in connection with them
    might be settled quickly without much dislocation and disorganisation of the needs of
    society and in a manner more adapted to conciliation and settlement than a
    determination of the respective rights and liabilities according to strict legal
    procedure and principles. The conflicts between capital and labour have now to be
    determined more from the standpoint of status than of contract. Without such an
    approach, the numerous problems that now arise for solution in the shape of
    industrial disputes cannot be tackled satisfactorily, and this is why every civilised
    government has thought of the machinery of conciliation officers, Boards and
    Tribunals for the effective settlement of disputes, (emphasis, added)
  18. The dynamics of industrial law, even if incongruous with popular understanding, is
    this first proposition we derive from Banerji:
    Legislation had to keep pace with the march of times and to provide for new
    situations. Social evolution is a process of constant growth, and the State cannot
    afford to stand still without taking adequate measures by means of legislation to solve
    large and momentous problems that arise in the industrial field from day to day
    almost.
  19. The second, though trite, guidance that we get is that we should not be beguiled by
    similar words in dissimilar statutes, contexts, subject-matters or socio-economic situations.
    The same words may mean one thing in one context and another in a different context. This is
    the reason why decisions on the meaning of particular words or collection of words found in
    other statutes are scarcely of much value when we have to deal with a specific statute of our
    own; they may persuade, but cannot pressure.
  20. We would only add that a developing country is anxious to preserve the smooth flow
    of goods and services, and interdict undue exploitation and, towards those ends, labour
    legislation is enacted and must receive liberal construction to fulfil its role.
  21. Let us get down to the actual amplitude and circumscription of the statutory concept
    of ‘industry’. Not a narrow but an enlarged acceptation is intended. This is supported by
    several considerations. Chandrasekhara Aiyar, J., observes:
    45
    Do the definitions of ‘industry’, ‘industrial dispute’ and ‘workman’ take in the
    extended significance, or exclude it? Though the word ‘undertaking’ in the definition
    of ‘industry’ is wedged in between business and trade on the one hand and
    manufacture on the other, and though therefore it might mean only a business or trade
    undertaking, still it must be remembered that if that were so, there was no need to use
    the word separately from business or trade. The wider import is attracted even more
    clearly when we look at the latter part of the definition which refers to “calling,
    service, employment, or industrial occupation or avocation of workmen”.
    “Undertaking” in the first part of the definition and “industrial occupation or
    avocation” in the second part obviously mean much more than what is ordinarily
    understood by trade or business. The definition was apparently intended to include
    within its scope what might not strictly be called a trade or business venture.
    So ‘industry’ overflows trade and business. Capital, ordinarily assumed to be a component of
    ‘industry’, is an expendable item so far as statutory ‘industry’ is concerned. To reach this
    conclusion, the Court referred to ‘public utility service’ [Section 2(n)] and argued: (SCR p.
    312)
    A public utility service such as railways, telephones and the supply of power,
    light or water to the public may be carried on by private companies or business
    corporations. Even conservancy or sanitation may be so carried on, though after the
    introduction of local self-government this work has in almost every country been
    assigned as a duty to local bodies like our Municipalities or District Boards or Local
    Boards. A dispute in these services between employers and workmen is an industrial
    dispute, and the proviso to Section 10 lays down that where such a dispute arises and
    a notice under Section 22 has been given, the appropriate Government shall make a
    reference under the sub-section. If the public utility service is carried on by a
    corporation like a Municipality which is the creature of a statute, and which functions
    under the limitations imposed by the statute, does it cease to be an industry for this
    reason? The only ground on which one could say that what would amount to the
    carrying on of an industry if it is done by a private person ceases to be so if the same
    work is carried on by a local body like a Municipality is that in the latter there is
    nothing like the investment of any capital or the existence of a profit earning motive
    as there generally is in a business. But neither the one nor the other seems a sine quo
    non or necessary element in the modern conception of industry, (emphasis, added)
  22. Absence of capital does not negative ‘industry’. Nay, even charitable services do not
    necessarily cease to be ‘industries’ definitionally although popularly charity is not industry.
    Interestingly, the learned Judge dealt with the point. After enumerating typical municipal
    activities he concluded: (SCR p. 313)
    Some of these functions may appertain to and partake of the nature of an
    industry, while others may not. For instance, there is a necessary element of
    distinction between the supply of power and light to the inhabitants of a Municipality
    and the running of charitable hospitals and dispensaries for the aid of the poor. In
    ordinary parlance, the former might be regarded as an industry but not the latter. The
    very idea underlying the entrustment of such duties or functions to local bodies is not
    46
    to take them out of the sphere of industry but to secure the substitution of public
    authorities in the place of private employers and to eliminate the motive of profitmaking as far as possible. The levy of taxes for the maintenance of the services of
    sanitation and the conservancy or the supply of light and water is a method adopted
    and devised to make up for the absence of capital. The undertaking or the service will
    still remain within the ambit of what we understand by industry though it is carried
    on with the aid of taxation, and no immediate material gain by way of profit is
    envisaged, (emphasis, added)
  23. The contention that charitable undertakings are not industries is, by this token,
    untenable.
  24. Another argument pertinent to our discussion is the sweep of the expression ‘trade’.
  25. In short, ‘trade’ embraces functions of local authorities, even professions, thus
    departing from popular notions. Another facet of the controversy is next touched upon – i.e.
    profit-making motive is not a sine qua non of ‘industry’, functionally or definitionally. For
    this, Powers, J. in Federated Municipal and Shire Employees’ Union of Australia v.
    Melbourne Corporation [26 CLR 508 (Aus.)] was quoted with emphatic approval where the
    Australian High Court considered an industrial legislation:
    So far as the question in this case is concerned, as the argument proceeded the
    ground mostly relied upon (after the Councils were held not to be exempt as State
    instrumentalities) was that the work was not carried on by the municipal corporations
    for profit in the ordinary sense of the term, although it would generally speaking be
    carried on by the Councils themselves to save contractors’ profits. If that argument
    were sufficient, then a philanthropist who acquired a clothing factory and employed
    the same employees as the previous owner had employed would not be engaged in an
    occupation about which an industrial dispute could arise, if he distributed the clothes
    made to the poor free of charge or even if he distributed them to the poor at the bare
    cost of production. If the contention of the respondents is correct, a private company
    carrying on a ferry would be engaged in an industrial occupation. If a municipal
    corporation carried it on, it would not be industrial. The same argument would apply
    to baths, bridge-building, quarries, sanitary contracts, gas-making for lighting streets
    and public halls, municipal building of houses or halls, and many other similar
    industrial undertakings. Even coal-mining for use on municipal railways or tramways
    would not be industrial work if the contention of the respondents is correct. If the
    works in question are carried out by contractors or by private individuals it is said to
    be industrial, but not industrial within the meaning of the Arbitration Act or
    Constitution if carried out by municipal corporations. I cannot accept that view.”
    (emphasis added)
  26. The negation of profit motive, as a telling test against ‘industry’, is clear from this
    quote.
  27. All the indicia of ‘industry’ are packed into the judgment which condenses the
    conclusion tersely to hold that ‘industries’ will cover ‘branches of work that can be said to be
    analogous to the carrying out of a trade or business’. The case, read as a whole, contributes
    47
    to industrial jurisprudence, with special reference to the Act, a few positive facets and knocks
    down a few negative fixations. Governments and municipal and statutory bodies may run
    enterprises which do not for that reason cease to be industries. Charitable activities may also
    be industries. Undertakings, sans profit motive, may well be industries. Professions are not
    ipso facto out of the pale of industries. Any operation carried on in a manner analogous to
    trade or business may legitimately be statutory ‘industry’. The popular limitations on the
    concept of industry do not amputate the ambit of legislative generosity in Section 2(j).
    Industrial peace and the smooth supply to the community are among the aims and objects the
    Legislature had in view, as also the nature, variety range and areas of disputes between
    employers and employees. These factors must inform the construction of the provision.
  28. The limiting role of Banerji must also be noticed so that a total view is gained. For
    instance, ‘analogous to trade or business’ cuts down ‘undertaking’, a word of fantastic sweep.
    Spiritual undertakings, casual undertakings, domestic undertakings, war waging, policing,
    justicing, legislating, tax collecting and the like are, prima facie, pushed out. Wars are not
    merchantable, nor justice saleable, nor divine grace marketable. So, the problem shifts to what
    is “analogous to trade or business”. As we proceed to the next set of cases we come upon the
    connotation of other expressions like ‘calling’ and get to grips with the specific organisations
    which call for identification in the several appeals before us.
  29. At this stage, a close-up of the content and contours of the controversial words
    ‘analogous etc.’, which have consumed considerable time of Counsel, may be taken. To be
    fair to Banerji, the path-finding decision which conditioned and canalised and fertilised
    subsequent juristic-humanistic ideation, we must show fidelity to the terminological
    exactitude of the seminal expression used and search carefully for its import. The prescient
    words are: branches of work that can be said to be analogous to the carrying out of a ‘trade
    or business’. The same judgment has negatived the necessity for profit-motive and included
    charity impliedly, has virtually equated private sector and public sector operations and has
    even perilously hinted at ‘professions’ being ‘trade’. In this perspective, the comprehensive
    reach of ‘analogous’ activities must be measured. The similarity stressed relates to ‘branches
    of work’; and more; the analogy will trade or business is in the ‘carrying out’ of the economic
    adventure. So, the parity is in the modus operandi, in the working – not in the purpose of the
    project nor in the disposal of the proceeds but in the organisation of the venture, including the
    relations between the two limbs, viz., labour and management. If the mutual relations, the
    method of employment and the process of co-operation in the carrying out of the work bear
    close resemblance to the organization, method, remuneration, relationship of employer and
    employee and the like, then it is industry, otherwise not. This is the kernel of the decision. An
    activity oriented, not motive based, analysis.
  30. The landmark Australian case of Melbourne Corporation, which was heavily relied
    on in Banerji may engage us. That ruling contains dicta, early in the century, which make
    India in forensic fabianism, sixty years after in the ‘socialist’ Republic, blush. The apart, the
    discussion in the leading judgments dealing with ‘industry’ from a constitutional angle but
    relying on statute similar to ours, is instructive. For instance, consider the promptings of profit
    as a condition of ‘industry’; Highness, J. crushes that credo thus:
    48
    The purpose of profit-making can hardly be the criterion. If it were, the labourers
    who excavated the underground passage for the Duke of Portland’s whim, 01 the
    labourers who build (for pa,)) a tower of Babel or a Pyramid, could not be parties to
    an ‘industrial dispute.
    The worker-oriented perspective is underscored by Isaacs and Rich JJ.: It is at the same time,
    as is perceived, contended on the part of labour, that matters even indirectly prejudicially
    affecting the workers are within the sphere of dispute.
  31. Now, the cornerstone of industrial law is well laid by Banerji, supported by Lord
    Mayor of the City of Melbourne.
    65 A chronological survey of post-Banerji decisions of this Court, with accent on the
    juristic contribution registered by them, may be methodical. Thereafter, cases in alien
    jurisdictions and derivation of guidelines may be attempted. Even here, we may warn
    ourselves that the literal latitude of the words in the definition cannot be allowed grotesquely
    inflationary play but must be read down to accord with the broad industrial sense of the
    nation’s economic community of which Labour is an integral part. To bend beyond credible
    limits is to break with facts, unless language leaves no option. Forensic inflation of the sense
    of words shall not lead to an adaptation breakdown outraging the good sense of even radical
    realists. After all, the Act has been drawn on an industrial canvas to solve the problems of
    industry, not of chemistry. A functional focus and social control desideratum must be in the
    mind’s eye of the Judge.
  32. The two landmark cases, The Corporation of the City of Nagpur v. Its Employees
    [AIR 1960 SC 675] and State of Bombay v. The Hospital Mazdoor Sabha [AIR 1960 SC
    610] may now be analysed in the light of what we have just said. Filling the gaps in the
    Banerji decision and the authoritative connotation of the fluid phrase ‘analogous to trade and
    business’ were attempted in these twin decisions. To be analogous is to resemble in functions
    relevant to the subject, as between like features of two apparently different things. So, some
    kinship through resemblance to trade or business, is the key to the problem, if Banerji is the
    guide star. Partial similarity postulates selectivity of characteristics for comparability.
    Wherein lies the analogy to trade or business, is then the query.
  33. Sri Justice Subba Rao, with uninhibited logic, chases this thought and reaches certain
    tests in Nagpur Municipality, speaking for a unanimous Bench. We respectfully agree with
    much of his reasoning and proceed to deal with the decision. If the ruling were right, as we
    think it is, the riddle of ‘industry’ is resolved in some measure. Although foreign decisions,
    words and phrases, lexical plenty and definitions from other legislations, were read before us
    to stress the necessity of direct co-operation between employer and employees in the essential
    product of the undertaking, of the need for the commercial motive, of service to the
    community etc., as implied inarticulately in the concept of ‘industry’, we bypass them as but
    marginally persuasive. The rulings of this Court, the language and scheme of the Act and the
    well-known canons of construction exert real pressure on our judgment. And, in this latter
    process, next to Banerji comes Corporation of Nagpur which spreads the canvas wide and
    illumines the expression ‘analogous to trade or business’, although it comes a few days after
    Hospital Mazdoor Sabha decided by the same Bench.
    49
  34. To be sure of our approach on a wider basis let us cast a glance at internationally
    recognised concepts vis-a-vis industry. The International Labour Organisation has had
    occasion to consider freedom of association for labour as a primary right and collective
    bargaining followed by strikes, if necessary, as a derivative right. The question has arisen as
    to whether public servants employed in the crucial functions of the government fall outside
    the orbit of industrial conflict. Convention 98 concerning the Application of the Principles of
    the Right to Organise and to Bargain Collectively, in Article 6 states:
    This Convention does not deal with the position of public servants engaged in the
    administration of the State, nor shall it be construed as prejudicing their rights or
    status in any way.
    Thus, it is well-recognised that public servants in the key sectors of administration stand out
    of the industrial sector. The Committee of Experts of the ILO had something to say about the
    carving out of the public servants from the general category.
  35. Incidentally, it may be useful to note certain clear statements made by ILO on the
    concept of industry, workmen and industrial dispute, not with clear-cut legal precision but
    with sufficient particularity for general purposes although looked at from a different angle.
    We quote from Freedom of Association, Second Edition, 1976, which is a digest of decisions
    of the Freedom of Association Committee of the Governing Body of the ILO:
  36. Civil servants and other workers in the employ of the State
    (250) Convention 98, and in particular Article 4 thereof concerning the
    encouragement and promotion of collective bargaining, applies both to the private sector
    and to nationalised undertakings and public bodies, it being possible to exclude from such
    application public servants engaged in the administration of the State. (Report 141, Case
    729, para 15.)
    (251) Convention 98, which mainly concerns collective bargaining, permits (Article
    6) the exclusion of “public servants engaged in the administration of the State”. In this
    connection, the Committee of Experts on the Application of Conventions and
    Recommendations has pointed out that, while the concept of public servant may vary to
    some degree under the various national legal systems, the exclusion from the scope of the
    Convention of persons employed by the State or in the public sector, who do not act as
    agents of the public authority (even though they may be granted a status identical with
    that of public officials engaged in the administration of the State) is contrary to the
    meaning of the Convention. The distinction to be drawn, according to the Committee,
    would appear to be basically between civil servants employed in various capacities in
    government ministries or comparable bodies on the one hand and other persons employed
    by the government, by public undertakings or by independent public corporations.
    (Report 116, Case 598, para 377; Report 121, Case 635, para 81; Report 143, Case 764,
    para 87).
    (254) With regard to a complaint concerning the right of teachers to engage in
    collective bargaining, the Committees, in the light of the principles contained in
    Convention 98 draw attention to the desirability of promoting voluntary collective
    50
    bargaining, according to national conditions, with a view to the regulation of terms and
    conditions of employment. (Report 110, Case 573, para 194.)
    (255) The Committee has pointed out that Convention 98, dealing with the promotion
    of collective bargaining, covers all public servants who do not act as agents of the public
    authority, and consequently, among these employers of the postal and telecommunications service. (Report 139, Case 725, para 278.)
    (256) Civil aviation technicians working under the jurisdiction of the armed forces
    cannot be considered, in view of the nature of their activities, as belonging to the armed
    forces and as such liable to be excluded from the guarantees laid down in Convention 98;
    the rule contained in Article 4 of the convention concerning collective bargaining should
    be applied to them. (Report 116, Case 598, paras 375-378.)
  37. This divagation was calculated only to emphasise certain fundamentals in
    international industrial thinking which accord with a wider conceptual acceptation for
    ‘industry’. The wings of the word ‘industry’ have been spread wide in Section 2(j) and this
    has been brought out in the decision in Corporation of Nagpur. That case was concerned
    with a dispute between a municipal body and its employees. The major issue considered there
    was the meaning of the much disputed expression “analogous to the carrying on of a trade or
    business”. Municipal undertakings are ordinarily industries as Baroda Borough Municipality
    [AIR 1957 SC 110] held. Even so the scope of ‘industry’ was investigated by the Bench in the
    City of Nagpur which affirmed Banerji and Baroda. The Court took the view that the words
    used in the definition were prima facie of the widest import and declined to curtail the width
    of meaning by invocation of noscitur a sociis. Even so, the Court was disinclined to spread
    the net too wide by expanding the elastic expressions ‘calling’, ‘service’, ‘employment’ and
    ‘handicraft’. To be over-inclusive may be impractical and so while accepting the enlargement
    of meaning by the device of inclusive definition the Court cautioned: (SCR p. 952)
    But such a wide meaning appears to over-reach the objects for which the Act was
    passed. It is, therefore, necessary to limit its scope on permissible grounds, having
    regard to the aim, scope and the object of the whole Act.
  38. After referring to the rule in Heydon case [(1584) ER 637], Subba Rao, J. proceeded
    to outline the ambit of industry thus:
    The word ‘employers’ in clause (a) and the word ‘employees’ in clause (b)
    indicate that the fundamental basis for the application of the definition is the
    existence of that relationship. The cognate definitions of ‘industrial dispute’,
    ‘employer’, ‘employee’, also support it. The long title of the Act as well as its
    preamble shows that the Act was passed to make provision for the promotion of
    industries and peaceful and amicable settlement of disputes between employers and
    employees in an organised activity by conciliation and arbitration and for certain
    other purposes. If the preamble is read with the historical background for the passing
    of the Act, it is manifest that the Act was introduced as an important step in achieving
    social justice. The Act seeks to ameliorate the service conditions of the workers, to
    provide a machinery for resolving their conflicts and to encourage co-operative effort
    in the service of the community. The history of labour legislation both in England
    51
    and India also shows that it was aimed more to ameliorate the conditions of service of
    the labour in organised activities than to anything else. The Act was not intended to
    reach the personal services which do not depend upon the employment of a labour
    force.
  39. Whether the exclusion of personal services is warranted may be examined a little
    later.
  40. The Court proceeded to carve out the negative factors which, notwithstanding the
    literal width of the language of the definition, must, for other compelling reasons, be kept out
    of the scope of industry. For instance, sovereign functions of the State cannot be included
    although what such functions are has been aptly termed ‘the primary and inalienable functions
    of a constitutional government’. Even here we may point out the ineptitude of relying on the
    doctrine of regal powers. That has reference, in this context, to the Crown’s liability in tort
    and has nothing to do with Industrial Law. In any case, it is open to Parliament to make law
    which governs the State’s relations with its employees. Articles 309 to 311 of the Constitution
    of India, the enactments dealing with the Defence Forces and other legislation dealing with
    employment under statutory bodies may, expressly or by necessary implication, exclude the
    operation of the Industrial Disputes Act, 1947. That is a question of interpretation and
    statutory exclusion; but, in the absence of such provision of law, it may indubitably be
    assumed that the key aspects of public administration like public justice stand out of the circle
    of industry. Even here, as has been brought out from the excerpts of ILO documents, it is not
    every employee who is excluded but only certain categories primarily engaged and
    supportively employed in the discharge of the essential functions of constitutional
    government. In a limited way, this head of exclusion has been recognised throughout.
  41. Although we are not concerned in this case with those categories of employees who
    particularly come under departments charged with the responsibility for essential
    constitutional functions of government, it is appropriate to state that if there are industrial
    units severable from the essential functions and possess an entity of their own it may be
    plausible to hold that the employees of those units are workmen and those undertakings are
    industries. A blanket exclusion of every one of the host of employees engaged by government
    in departments falling under general, rubrics like, justice, defence, taxation, legislature, may
    not necessarily be thrown out of the umbrella of the Act. We say no more except to observe
    that closer exploration, not summary rejection, is necessary.
  42. The Court proceeded, in the Corporation of Nagpur case, to pose for itself the import
    of the words ‘analogous to the carrying out of a trade or business’ and took the view that the
    emphasis was more on ‘the nature of the organised activity implicit in trade or business than
    to equate the other activities with trade or business’. Obviously, non-trade operations were in
    many cases ‘industry’.
  43. It is useful to remember that the Court rejected the test attempted by Counsel in the
    case:
    It is said that unless there is a quid pro quo for the service it cannot be an
    industry. This is the same argument, namely, that the service must be in the nature of
    trade in a different garb.
    52
    We agree with this observation and with the further observation that there is no merit in
    the plea that unless the public who are benefited by the services pay in cash, the services so
    rendered cannot be industry. Indeed, the signal service rendered by the Corporation of
    Nagpur is to dispel the idea of profit-making.
    Monetary considerations for service is, therefore, not an essential characteristic of
    industry in a modern State.
  44. Even according to the traditional concepts of English Law, profit has to be
    disregarded when ascertaining whether an enterprise is a business:
  45. Disregard of Profit.- Profit or the intention to make profit is not an essential
    part of the legal definition of a trade or business; and payment or profit does not
    constitute a trade or business that which would not otherwise be such.
  46. Does the badge of industrialism, broadly understood, banish, from its fold, education?
    This question needs fuller consideration, as it has been raised in this batch of appeals and has
    been answered in favour of employers by this Court in the Delhi University [AIR 1963 SC
    1873] case. But since Subba Rao, J., has supportively cited Isaacs, J. in School Teachers’
    Association [(1929) 41 CLR 569 (Aus)], which relates to the same problem, we may, even
    here, prepare the ground by dilating on the subject with special reference to the Australian
    case. That learned Judge expressed surprise at the very question:
    The basic question raised by this case, strange as it may seem, is whether the occupation
    of employees engaged in education, itself universally recognised as the key industry to all
    skilled occupations, is ‘industrial’ within the meaning of the Constitution.
  47. The employers argued that it was fallacious to spin out ‘industry’ from ‘education’
    and the logic was a specious economic doctrine. Isaacs, J., with unsparing sting and in
    fighting mood, stated and refuted the plea:
    The theory was that society is industrially organised for the production and
    distribution of wealth in the sense of tangible, ponderable, corpuscular wealth, and
    therefore an “industrial dispute” cannot possibly occur except where there is
    furnished to the public – the consumers – by the combined efforts of employers and
    employed, wealth of that nature. Consequently, say the employers, “education” not
    being “wealth” in that sense, there never can be an “industrial dispute” between
    employers and employed engaged in the avocation of education, regardless of the
    wealth derived by the employers from the joint co-operation.
    The contention sounds like an echo from the dark ages of industry and political
    economy. It not merely ignores the constant currents of life around us, which is the
    real danger in deciding questions of this nature, but it also forgets the memorable
    industrial organization of the nations, not for the production or distribution of
    material wealth, but for services, national service, as the service of organized industry
    must always be. Examination of this contention will not only completely dissipate it,
    but will also serve to throw material light on the question in hand generally. The
    contention is radically unsound for two great reasons. It erroneously conceives the
    object of national industrial organization and thereby unduly limits the meaning of
    53
    the terms “production” and “wealth” when used in that connection. But it further
    neglects the fundamental character of “industrial disputes” as a distinct and insistent
    phenomenon of modern society. Such disputes are not simply a claim to share the
    material wealth jointly produced and capable of registration in statistics. At heart they
    are a struggle, constantly becoming more intense on the part of the employed group
    engaged in co-operation with the employing group in rendering services to the
    community essential for a higher general human welfare, to share in that welfare in a
    greater degree …. That contention, if acceded to, would be revolutionary…. How
    could it reasonably be said that a comic song or a jazz performance, or the
    representation of a comedy, or a ride in a tramcar or motor-bus, piloting a ship,
    lighting a lamp or showing a moving picture is more “material” as wealth than
    instruction, either cultural or vocational? Indeed, to take one instance, a workman
    who travels in a tramcar a mile from his home to his factory is no more efficient for
    his daily task than if he walked ten yards, whereas his technical training has a direct
    effect in increasing output. If music or acting or personal transportation is admitted to
    be “industrial” because each is productive of wealth to the employer as his business
    undertaking, then an educational establishment stands on the same footing. But if
    education is excluded for the reason advanced, how are we to admit barbers, hairdressers, taxi-car drivers, furniture removers, and other occupations that readily
    suggest themselves? And yet the doctrine would admit manufacturers of intoxicants
    and producers of degrading literature and pictures, because these are considered to be
    “wealth”. The doctrine would concede, for instance, that establishments for the
    training of performing dogs, or of monkeys simulating human behaviour, would be
    “industrial”, because one would have increased material wealth, that is, a more
    valuable dog or monkey, in the sense that one could exchange it for more money. If
    parrots are taught to say “Pretty Polly” and to dance on their perch, that is, by
    concession, industrial, because it is the production of wealth. But if Australian youths
    are trained to read and write their language correctly and in other necessary elements
    of culture and vocation making them more efficient citizens, fitting them with more
    01 less directness to take their place in the general industrial ranks of the nation and
    to render the services required by the community, that training is said not to be
    wealth and the work done by teachers employed is said not to be industrial.
  48. So long as services are part of the wealth of a nation – and it is obscurantist to object
    to it – educational services are wealth, are ‘industrial’. We agree with Isaacs, J.
  49. More closely analysed, we may ask ourselves, as Isaacs, J. did, whether, if private
    scholastic establishments carried on teaching on the same lines as the State schools, giving
    elementary education free, and charging fees for the higher subjects, providing the same
    curriculum and so on, by means of employed teachers, would such a dispute as we have here
    be an industrial dispute?…. “I have already indicated my view”, says Isaacs, J. “that education
    so provided constitutes in itself an independent industrial operation as a service rendered to
    the community”. Charles Dickens evidently thought so when ninety years ago Squeers called
    his school “the shop” and prided himself on Nickleby’s being “cheap” at £ 5 a year and
    commensurate living conditions. The world has not turned back since then. In 1926 the
    54
    Committee on Industry and Trade, in their report to the British Prime Minister, included
    among “Trade Unions” those called “teaching”. It there appears that in 1897 there were six
    unions with a total membership of 45,319, and in 1924 there were seventeen unions with a
    membership of 1,94,946. The true position of education in relation to the actively operative
    trades is not really doubtful. Education, cultural and vocational, is now and is daily becoming
    as much the artisan’s capital and tool, and to a great extent his safeguard against
    unemployment, as the employers’ banking credit and insurance policy are part of his means to
    carry on the business. There is at least as much reason for including the educational
    establishments in the constitutional power as “labour” services, as there is to include
    insurance companies as “capital” services.
  50. We have extensively excerpted from the vigorous dissent because the same position
    holds good for India which is emerging from feudal illiteracy to industrial education. In
    Gandhi’s India basic education and handicraft merge and in the latter half of our century
    higher education involves field studies, factory training, house-surgeoncy and clinical
    education; and, sans such technological training and education in humanities, industrial
    progress is self-condemned. If education and training are integral to industrial and agricultural
    activities, such services are part of industry even if highbrowism may be unhappy to
    acknowledge it. It is a class-conscious, inegalitarian outlook with an elitist aloofness which
    makes some people shrink from accepting educational institutions, vocational or other, as
    industries. The definition is wide, embraces training for industry which, in turn ensconces all
    processes of producing goods and services by employer-employee co-operation. Education is
    the nidus of industrialization and itself is industry.
  51. We may consider certain aspects of this issue while dealing with later cases of our
    Court. Suffice it to say, the unmanning argument of Isaacs, J. has been specifically approved
    in Corporation of Nagpur and Hospital Mazdoor Sabha in a different aspect.
  52. Now we revert to the more crucial part of Corporation of Nagpur. It is meaningful to
    notice that in that case, the Court, in its incisive analysis, department by department of
    variform municipal services, specifically observed:
    Education Department: This department looks after the primary education, i.e.,
    compulsory primary education within the limits of the Corporation. (See the evidence
    of witness 1 for party 1). This service can equally be done by private persons. This
    department satisfies the other tests. The employees of this department coming under
    the definition of “employees” under the Act would certainly be entitled to the
    benefits of the Act.
  53. The substantial break-through achieved by this decision in laying bare the
    fundamentals of ‘industry’ in its wider sense deserves mention. The ruling tests are clear. The
    ‘analogous’ species of quasi-trade qualify for becoming ‘industry’ if the nature of the
    organized activity implicit in a trade or business is shared by them. (See p. 960, the entire
    organisational activity). It is not necessary to ‘equate the other activities with trade or
    business’. The pith and substance of the matter is that the structural, organisational,
    engineering aspect, the crucial industrial relations like wages, leave and other service
    conditions as well as characteristic business methods (not motives) in running the enterprise,
    55
    govern the conclusion. Presence of profit motive is expressly negated as a criterion. Even the
    quid pro quo theory – which is the same monetary object in a milder version – has been
    dismissed. The subtle distinction, drawn in lovely lines and pressed with emphatic effect by
    Sri Tarkunde, between gain and profit, between no-profit no-loss basis having different results
    in the private and public sectors, is fascinating but, in the rough and tumble, and sound and
    fury of industrial life, such nuances break down and nice refinements defeat. For the same
    reason, we are disinclined to chase the differential ambits of the first and the second parts of
    Section 2(j). Both read together and each viewed from the angle of employer or employee and
    applied in its sphere, as the learned Attorney General pointed out, will make sense. If the
    nature of the activity is para-trade or quasi-business, it is of no moment that it is undertaken
    in the private sector, joint sector, public sector, philanthropic sector or labour sector; it is
    ‘industry’. It is the human sector, the way the employer-employee relations are set up and
    processed that gives rise to claims, demands, tensions, adjudications, settlements, truce and
    peace in industry. That is the raison d’etre of industrial law itself.
  54. Two seminal guidelines of great moment flow from this decision: (1) the primary and
    predominant activity test; and (2) the integrated activity test. The concrete application of these
    two-fold tests is illustrated in the very case. We may set out in the concise words of Subba
    Rao, J., the sum-up: (SCR p. 961)
    The result of the discussion may be summarized thus: (1) The definition of
    “industry” in the Act is very comprehensive. It is in two parts: one part defines it
    from the standpoint of the employer and the other from the standpoint of the
    employee. If an activity falls under either part of the definition, it will be an industry
    within the meaning of the Act. (2) The history of industrial disputes and the
    legislation recognizes the basic concept that the activity shall be an organized one
    and not that which pertains to private or personal employment. (3) The regal
    functions described as primary and inalienable functions of State though statutorily
    delegated to a corporation are necessarily excluded from the purview of the
    definition. Such regal functions shall be confined to legislative power, administration
    of law and judicial power. (4) If a service rendered by an individual or private person
    would be an industry, it would equally be an industry in the hands of a corporation.
    (5) If a service rendered- by a corporation is an industry, the employees in the
    departments connected with that service, whether financial, administrative or
    executive, would be entitled to the benefits of the Act. (6) If a department of a
    municipality discharged many functions, some pertaining to industry as defined in
    the Act and other non-industrial activities, the predominant functions of the
    department shall be the criterion for the purpose of the Act.
  55. By these tokens, which find assent from us, the tax department of the local body is
    ‘industry’. The reason is this:
    The scheme of the Corporation Act is that taxes and fees are collected in order to
    enable the municipality to discharge its statutory functions. If the functions so
    discharged are wholly or predominantly covered by the definition of “industry”, it
    would be illogical to exclude the tax department from the definition. While in the
    case of private individuals or firms services are paid in cash or otherwise, in the case
    56
    of public institutions, as the services are rendered to the public, the taxes collected
    from them constitute a fund for performing those services. As most of the services
    rendered by the municipality come under the definition of “industry”, we should hold
    that the employees of the tax department are also entitled to the benefits under the
    Act.
  56. The health department of the municipality too is held in that case to be ‘industry’ – a
    fact which is pertinent when we deal later with hospitals, dispensaries and health centres:
    This department looks after scavenging, sanitation, control of epidemics, control
    of food adulteration and running of public dispensaries. Private institutions can also
    render these services. It is said that the control of food adulteration and the control of
    epidemics cannot be done by private individuals and institutions. We do not see why.
    There can be private medical units to help in the control of epidemics for
    remuneration. Individuals may get the food articles purchased by them examined by
    the medical unit and take necessary action against guilty merchants. So too, they can
    take advantage of such a unit to prevent epidemics by having necessary inoculations
    and advice. This department also satisfies the other tests laid down by us, and is an
    industry within the meaning of the definition of “industry” in the Act.
  57. Even the General Administration Department is ‘industry’. Why?
    Every big company with different sections will have a general administration
    department. If the various departments collated with the department are industries,
    this department would also be a part of the industry. Indeed the efficient rendering of
    all the services would depend upon the proper working of this department, for,
    otherwise there would be confusion and chaos. The State Industrial Court in this case
    has held that all except five of the departments of the Corporation come under the
    definition of “industry” and if so, it follows that this department, dealing
    predominantly with industrial departments, is also an industry. Hence the employees
    of this department are also entitled to the benefits of this Act.
  58. Running right through are three tests: (a) the paramount and predominant duty
    criterion (p. 971); (b) the specific service being an integral, non-severable part of the same
    activity (p. 960) and (c) the irrelevance of the statutory duty aspect.
    It is said that the functions of this department are statutory and no private
    individual can discharge those statutory functions. The question is not whether the
    discharge of certain functions by the Corporation have statutory backing, but whether
    those functions can equally be performed by private individuals. The provisions of
    the Corporation Act and the by-laws prescribe certain specifications for submission
    of plans and for the sanction of the authorities concerned before the building is put
    up. The same thing can be done by a co-operative society or a private individual. Cooperative societies and private individuals can allot lands for building houses in
    accordance with the conditions prescribed by law in this regard. The services of this
    department are therefore analogous to those of a private individual with the
    difference that one has the statutory sanction b-’hind it and the other is governed by
    terms of contracts.
    57
    Be it noted that even co-operatives are covered by the learned Judge although we may deal
    with that matter a little later.
  59. The same Bench decided both Corporation of Nagpur and Hospital Mazdoor Sabha .
    This latter case may be briefly considered now. It repeals the profit motive and quid pro quo
    theory as having any bearing on the question. The wider import of Section 2(/) is accepted but
    it expels essential ‘sovereign activities’ from its scope.
  60. It is necessary to note that the hospital concerned in that case was run by Government
    for medical relief to the people. Nay more. It had a substantial educational and training role.
  61. A conspectus of the clauses has induced Gajendragadkar, J. to take note of the impact
    of provisions regarding public utility service also:
    If the object and scope of the statute are considered there would be no difficulty
    in holding that the relevant words of wide import have been deliberately used by the
    Legislature in defining “industry” in Section 2(j). The object of the Act was to make
    provision for the investigation and settlement of industrial disputes, and the extent
    and scope of its provisions would be realised if we bear in mind the definition of
    “industrial dispute” given by Section 2(k), of “wages” by Section 2(rr), “workman”
    by Section 2(s), and of “employer” by Section 2(g). Besides, the definition of a
    public utility service prescribed by Section 2(n) is very significant. One has merely to
    glance at the six categories of public utility service mentioned by Section 2(n) to
    realise that the rule of construction on which the appellant relies is inapplicable in
    interpreting the definition prescribed by Section 2(j).
    The positive delineation of ‘industry’ is set in these terms:
    (A)s a working principle it may be stated that an activity systematically or habitually
    undertaken for the production or distribution of goods or for the rendering of material
    services to the community at large or a part of such community with the help of
    employees is an undertaking. Such an activity generally involves the co-operation of
    the employer and the employees; and its object is the satisfaction of material human
    needs. It must be organised or arranged in a manner in which trade or business is
    generally organised or arranged. It must not be casual nor must it be for oneself nor
    for pleasure. Thus the manner in which the activity in question is organised or
    arranged, the condition of the co-operation between employer and the employee
    necessary for its success and its object to render material service to the community
    can be regarded as some of the features which are distinctive of activities to which
    Section 2(j) applies. Judged by this test there would be no difficulty in holding that
    the State is carrying on an undertaking when it runs the group of hospitals in
    question.
    Again,
    It is the character of the activity which decides the question as to whether the
    activity in question attracts the provision of Section 2(j); who conducts the activity
    and whether it is conducted for profit or not do not make a material difference.
    58
    By these tests even a free or charitable hospital is an industry. That the Court intended such a
    conclusion is evident:
    If that be so, if a private citizen runs a hospital without charging any fees from
    the patients treated in it, it would nevertheless be an undertaking under Section 2(j).
    Thus the character of the activity involved in running a hospital brings the institution
    of the hospital within Section 2(j).
  62. The ‘rub with the ruling’, if we may with great deference say so, begins when the
    Court inhibits itself from effectuating the logical thrust of its own crucial ratio: (SCR p. 876)
    (T)hough Section 2(j) uses words of very wide denotation, a line would have to be
    drawn in a fair and just manner so as to exclude some callings, services or
    undertakings. If all’ the words used are given their widest meaning, all services and
    all callings would come within the purview of the definition; even service rendered
    by a servant purely in a personal or domestic matter or even in a casual way would
    fall within the definition. It is not and cannot be suggested that in its wide sweep the
    word “service” is intended to include service howsoever rendered in whatsoever
    capacity and for whatsoever reason. We must, therefore, consider where the line
    should be drawn and what limitations can and should be reasonably implied in
    interpreting the wide words used in Section 2(j); and that no doubt is a somewhat
    difficult problem to decide.
    What is a ‘fair and just manner’? It must be founded on grounds justifiable by principle
    derived from the statute if it is not to be sublimation of subjective phobia, rationalization of
    interests or judicialisation of non-juristic negatives. And this hunch, in our respectful view,
    has been proved true not by positive pronouncement in the case but by two points suggested
    but left open. One relates to education and the other to professions. We will deal with them in
    due course.
    Liberal Professions
  63. When the delimiting line is drawn to whittle down a wide definition, a principled
    working test, not a projected wishful thought, should be sought. This conflict surfaced in the
    Solicitors [AIR 1962 SC 1080] case. Before us too, a focal point of contest was as to whether
    the liberal professions are ipso facto, excluded from ‘industry’. Two grounds were given by
    Gajendragadkar, J. for overruling Sri A. S. R. Chari’s submissions. The doctrine of direct cooperation and the features of liberal professions were given as good reasons to barricade
    professional enterprises from the militant clamour for more by lay labour. The learned Judge
    expressed himself on the first salvational plea:
    When in the Hospital case this Court referred to the organisation of the
    undertaking involving the co-operation of capital and labour or the employer and his
    employees, it obviously meant the co-operation essential and necessary/or the
    purpose of rendering material service or for the purpose of production. It would be
    realised that the concept of industry postulates partnership between capital and labour
    or between the employer and his employees. It is under this partnership that the
    employer contributes his capital and the employees their labour and the joint
    contribution of capital and labour leads directly to the production which the industry
    59
    has in view. In other words, the co-operation between capital and labour or between
    the employer and his employees which is treated as a working test in determining
    whether any activity amounts to an industry, is the co-operation which is directly
    involved in the production of goods or in the rendering of service. It cannot be
    suggested that every form or aspect of human activity in which capital and labour cooperate or employer and employees assist each other is an industry. The
    distinguishing feature of an industry is that for the production of goods or for the
    rendering of service, co-operation between capital and labour or between the
    employer and his employees must be direct and must be essential…. Co-operation to
    which the test refers must be co-operation between the employer and his employees
    which is essential for carrying out the purpose of the enterprise and the service to be
    rendered by the enterprise should be the direct outcome of the combined efforts of the
    employer and the employees.
  64. The second reason for exoneration is qualitative.
    Looking at this question in a broad and general way, it is not easy to conceive
    that a liberal profession like that of an attorney could have been intended by the
    Legislature to fall within the definition of “industry” under Section 2(j). The very
    concept of the liberal professions has its own special and distinctive features which
    do not readily permit the inclusion of the liberal professions into the four corners of
    industrial law. The essential basis of an industrial dispute is that it is a dispute arising
    between capital and labour in enterprises where capital and labour combine to
    produce commodities or to render service. This essential basis would be absent in the
    case of liberal professions. A person following a liberal profession does not carry on
    his profession in any intelligible sense with the active co-operation of his employees
    and the principal, if not the sole, capital which he brings into his profession is his
    special or peculiar intellectual and educational equipment. That is why on broad and
    general considerations which cannot be ignored, a liberal profession like that of an
    attorney must, we think, be deemed to be outside the definition of “industry” under
    Section 2(j).
  65. Let us examine these two tests. In the sophisticated, subtle, complex, assembly-line
    operations of modern enterprises, the test of ‘direct’ and ‘indirect’, ‘essential’ and
    ‘inessential’, will snap easily. In an American automobile manufactory, everything from
    shipping iron ore into and shipping cars out of the vast complex takes place with myriad
    major and minor jobs. A million administrative, marketing and advertising tasks are done.
    Which, out of this maze of chores, is direct? A battle may be lost if winter wear were shoddy.
    Is the army tailor a direct contributory?
  66. An engineer may lose a competitive contract if his typist typed wrongly or shabbily or
    despatched late. He is a direct contributory to the disaster. No lawyer or doctor can impress
    client or court if his public relations job or home work were poorly done, and that part
    depends on smaller men, adjuncts. Can the great talents in administration, profession, science
    or art shine if a secretary fades or faults? The whole theory of direct co-operation is an
    improvisation which, with great respect, hardly impresses.
    60
  67. Indeed, Hidayatullah, C.J., in Gymkhana Club Employees’ Union [AIR 1968 SC
    554] scouted the argument about direct nexus, making specific reference to the Solicitors’
    case:
    (T)he service of a solicitor was regarded as individual depending upon his personal
    qualifications and ability, to which the employees did not contribute directly or
    essentially. Their contribution, it was held, had no direct or essential nexus with the
    advice or services. In this way learned professions were excluded.
    To nail this essential nexus theory, Hidayatullah, C.J., argued:
    What partnership can exist between the company and/or Board of Directors on
    the one hand and the menial staff employed to sweep floors on the other? What direct
    and essential nexus is there between such employees and production? This proves
    that what must be established is the existence of an industry viewed from the angle of
    what the employer is doing and if the definition from the angle of the employer’s
    occupation is satisfied, all who render service and fall within the definition of
    workman come within the fold of industry irrespective of what they do. There is then
    no need to establish a partnership as such in the production of material goods or
    material services. Each person doing his appointed task in an organisation will be a
    part of the industry whether he attends to a loom or merely polishes door handles.
    The fact of employment as envisaged in the second part is enough provided there is
    an industry and the employee is a workman. The learned professions are not industry
    not because there is absence of such partnership but because viewed from the angle
    of the employer’s occupation, they do not satisfy the test.
  68. Although Gajendragadkar, J. in Solicitors’ case (supra) and Hidayatullah, J. in
    Gymkhana case agreed that the learned professions must be excluded, on the question of
    direct or effective contribution in partnership, they flatly contradicted each other. The
    reasoning on this part of the case which has been articulated in the Gymkhana Club
    Employees’ Union appeals to us. There is no need for insistence upon the principle of
    partnership, the doctrine of direct nexus or the contribution of values by employees. Every
    employee in a professional office, be he a para-legal assistant or full-fledged professional
    employee or, down the ladder, a mere sweeper or janitor, every one makes for the success of
    the office, even the mali who collects flowers and places a beautiful bunch in a vase on the
    table spreading fragrance and pleasantness around. The failure of anyone can mar even the
    success of everyone else. Efficient collectivity is the essence of professional success. We
    reject the plea that a member of a learned 01 liberal profession, for that sole reason, can selfexclude himself from operation of the Act.
  69. The professional immunity from labour’s demand for social justice because learned
    professions have a halo also stands on sandy foundation and, perhaps, validates G. B. Shaw’s
    witticism that all professions are conspiracies against the laity. After all, let us be realistic and
    recognise that we live in an age of experts alias professionals, each having his ethic,
    monopoly, prestige, power and profit. Proliferation of professions is a ubiquitous
    phenomenon and none but the tradition-bound will, agree that theirs is not a liberal
    61
    profession. Lawyers have their code. So too medics swearing by Hippocrates, chartered
    accountants and company secretaries and other autonomous nidi of know-how.
  70. All this adds up to the decanonisation of the noble professions. Assuming that a
    professional in our egalitarian ethos, is like any other man of common clay plying a trade or
    business, we cannot assent to the cult of the elite in carving out islands of exception to
    ‘industry’.
  71. The more serious argument of exclusion urged to keep the professions out of the
    coils of industrial disputes and the employees’ demands backed by agitations ‘red in tooth and
    claw’ is a sublimated version of the same argument. Professional expertise and excellence,
    with its occupational autonomy, ideology, learning, bearing and morality, holds aloft a
    standard of service which centres round the individual doctor, lawyer, teacher or auditor. This
    reputation and quality of special service being of the essence, the co-operation of the
    workmen in this core activity of professional offices is absent. The clerks and stenos, the bell
    boys and doormen, the sweepers and menials have no art or part in the soul of professional
    functions with its higher code of ethic and intellectual proficiency, their contribution being
    peripheral and low-grade, with no relevance to the clients’ wants and requirements. This
    conventional model is open to the sociological criticism that it is an ideological cloak
    conjured up by highborns, a posture of noblesse oblige which is incongruous with raw life,
    especially in the democratic third world and post-industrial societies. To hug the past is to
    materialize the ghost. The paradigms of professionalism are gone. In the large solicitors’
    firms, architects’ offices, medical polyclinics and surgeries, we find a humming industry, each
    section doing its work with its special flavour and culture and code, and making the end
    product worth its price. In a regular factory you have highly skilled technicians whose talent
    is of the essence, managers whose ability organizes and workmen whose coordinated input is,
    from one angle, secondary, from another, significant. Let us look at a surgery or walk into a
    realtor’s firm. What physician or surgeon will not kill if an attendant errs or clerk enters
    wrong or dispenses deadly dose? One such disaster somewhere in the assembly-line
    operations and the clientele will be scared despite the doctor’s distilled skill. The lawyer is no
    better and just cannot function without the specialised supportive tools of para-professionals
    like secretaries, librarians and law-knowing steno-typists or even the messengers and
    telephone girls. The mystique of professionalism easily melts in the hands of modern social
    scientists who have (as Watergate has shown in America and has India had its counterparts?)
    debunked and stripped the professional emperor naked. ‘Altruism’ has been exposed, cash has
    overcome craft nexus and if professionalism is a mundane ideology, then “profession” and
    “professional” are sociological contributions to the pile. Anyway, in the sophisticated
    organization of expert services, all occupations have central skills, an occupational code of
    ethics, a group culture, some occupational authority, and some permission to monopoly
    practice from the community. This incisive approach makes it difficult to ‘caste-ify’ or ‘classify’ the liberal professions as part and beyond the pale of ‘industry’ in our democracy. We
    mean no disrespect to the members of the professions. Even the judicial profession or
    administrative profession cannot escape the winds of social change. We may add that the
    modem world, particularly the third world, can hope for a human tomorrow only through
    professions for the people, through expertise at the service of the millions. Indian primitivism
    62
    can be banished only by pro bono publico professions in the field of law, medicine,
    education, engineering and what not. But that radicalism does not detract from the thesis that
    ‘industry’ does not spare professionals. Even so, the widest import may still self-exclude the
    little mofussil lawyer, the small rural medic or the country engineer, even though a hired
    sweeper or factotum assistant may work with him. We see no rationale in the claim to carve
    out islets. Look. A solicitor’s firm or a lawyer’s firm becomes successful not merely by the
    talent of a single lawyer but by the co-operative operations of several specialists, juniors and
    seniors. Likewise the ancillary services of competent stenographers, paralegal supportive
    services are equally important. The same test applies to other professions. The conclusion is
    inevitable that contribution to the success of the institution – every professional unit has an
    institutional goodwill and reputation – comes not merely from the professional or specialist
    but from all those whose excellence in their respective parts makes for the total proficiency.
    We have, therefore, no doubt that the claim for exclusion on the score of liberal professions is
    unwarranted from a functional or definitional angle. The flood-gates of exemption from the
    obligations under the Act will be opened if professions flow out of its scope.
  72. Many callings may clamour to be regarded as liberal professions. In an age when
    traditions have broken down and the old would professions of liberal descent have begun to
    resort to commercial practices (even legally, as in America, or factually, as in some other
    countries) exclusion under this new label will be infliction of injury on the statutory intent and
    effect.
  73. The result of this discussion is that the Solicitors’ case is wrongly decided and must,
    therefore, be overruled. We must hasten, however, to repeat that a small category, perhaps
    large in numbers in the mofussil, may not squarely fall within the definition of industry. A
    single lawyer, a rural medical practitioner or urban doctor with a little assistant and/of menial
    servant may ply a profession but may not be said to run an industry. That is not because the
    employee does not make a contribution nor because the profession is too high to be classified
    as a trade or industry with its commercial connotations but because there is nothing like
    organised labour in such employment. The image of industry or even quasi-industry is one of
    a plurality of workmen, not an isolated 01 single little assistant or attendant. The latter
    category is more or less like personal avocation for livelihood taking some paid or part-time
    from another. The whole purpose of the Industrial Disputes Act is to focus on resolution of
    industrial disputes and regulation of industrial relations and not to meddle with every little
    carpenter in a village or bla ksmith in a town who sits with his son or assistant to work for the
    customers who trek in. The ordinary spectacle of a cobbler and his assistant or a cycle repairer
    with a helper, we come across in the pavements of cities and towns, repels the idea of industry
    and industrial dispute. For this reason, which applies all along the line, to small professions,
    petty handicraftsmen, domestic servants and the like, the solicitor or doctor or rural engineer,
    even like the butcher, the baker and the candle-stick maker, with an assistant or without, does
    not fall within the definition of industry. In regular industries, of course, even a few
    employees are enough to bring them within Section 2(7). Otherwise automated industries will
    slip through the net.
    Education
    63
  74. We will now move on to a consideration of education as an industry. If the triple
    tests of systematic activity, co-operation between employer and employee and production of
    goods and services were alone to be applied, a University, a college, a research institute or
    teaching institution will be an industry. But in University of Delhi [AIR 1963 SC 1873] it was
    held that the Industrial Tribunal was wrong in regarding the University as an industry because
    it would be inappropriate to describe education as an industrial activity. Gajendragadkar, J.
    agreed in his judgment that the employer-employee test was satisfied and co-operation
    between the two was also present. Undoubtedly, education is a sublime cultural service,
    technological training and personality-builder. A man without- education is a brute and
    nobody can quarrel with the proposition that education, in its spectrum, is significant service
    to the community. We have already given extracts from Australian Judge Isaacs, J. to
    substantiate the thesis that education is not merely industry but the mother of industries. A
    philistinic, illiterate society will be not merely uncivilised but incapable of industrialisation.
    Nevertheless Gajendragadkar, J. observed:
    It would, no doubt, sound somewhat strange that education should be described
    as industry and the teachers as workmen within the meaning of the Act, but if the
    literal construction for which the respondents contend is accepted, that consequence
    must follow.
    Why is it strange to regard education as an industry? Its respectability? Its lofty character? Its
    professional stamp? Its cloistered virtue which cannot be spoiled by the commercial
    implications and the raucous voices of workmen? Two reasons are given to avoid the
    conclusion that imparting education is an industry. The first ground relied on by the Court is
    based upon the preliminary conclusion that teachers are not ‘workmen’ by definition. Perhaps,
    they are not, because teachers do not do manual work or technical work. We are not too sure
    whether it is proper to disregard, with contempt, manual work and separate it from education,
    nor are we too sure whether in our technological universe, education has to be excluded.
    However, that may be a battle to be waged on a later occasion by litigation and we do not
    propose to pronounce on it at present. The Court, in the University of Delhi, proceeded on
    that assumption viz. that teachers are not workmen, which we will adopt to test the validity of
    the argument. The reasoning of the Court is best expressed in the words of Gajendragadkar,
    J.:
    It is common ground that teachers employed by educational institutions, whether
    the said institutions are imparting primary, secondary, collegiate or post-graduate
    education, are not workmen under Section 2(s), and so, it follows that the whole body
    of employees with whose co-operation the work of imparting education is carried on
    by educational institutions do not fall within the purview of Section 2(s), and any
    disputes between them and the institutions which employed them are outside the
    scope of the Act. In other words, if imparting education is an industry under Section
    2(j), the bulk of the employees being outside the purview of the Act, the only
    disputes which can fall within the scope of the Act are those which arise between
    such institutions and their subordinate staff, the members of which may fall under
    Section 2(s). In our opinion, having regard to the fact that the work of education is
    primarily and exclusively carried on with the assistance of the labour and co-
    64
    operation of teachers, the omission of the whole class of teachers from the definition
    prescribed by Section 2(s) has an important bearing and significance in relation to the
    problem which we are considering. It could not have been the policy of the Act that
    education should be treated as industry for the benefit of a very minor and
    insignificant number of persons who may be employed by educational institutions to
    carry on the duties of the subordinate staff. Reading Section 2(g), (j) and (s) together,
    we are inclined to hold that the work of education carried on by educational
    institutions like the University of Delhi is not an industry within the meaning of the
    Act.
  75. The second argument which appealed to the Court to reach its conclusion is that:
    “the distinctive purpose and ‘object of education would make it very difficult to assimilate it
    to the position of any trade, business or calling or service within the meaning of Section 2(j)”.
    Why so? The answer is given by the learned Judge himself:
    Education seeks to build up the personality of the pupil by assisting his physical,
    intellectual, moral and emotional development. To speak of this educational process
    in terms of industry sounds so completely incongruous that one is not surprised that
    the Act has deliberately so defined workman under Section 2(s) as to exclude
    teachers from its scope. Under the sense of values recognised both by the traditional
    .and conservative as well as the modern and progressive social outlook, teaching and
    teachers are, no doubt, assigned a high place of honour and it is obviously necessary
    and desirable that teaching and teachers should receive the respect that is due to
    them. A proper sense of values would naturally hold teaching and teachers in high
    esteem, though power or wealth may not be associated with them. It cannot be denied
    that the concept of social justice is wide enough to include teaching and teachers, and
    the requirement that teachers should receive proper emoluments and other amenities
    which is essentially based on social justice cannot be disputed; but the effect of
    excluding teachers from Section 2(s) is only this that the remedy available for the
    betterment of their financial prospects does not fall under the Act. It is well-known
    that Education Departments of the State Governments as well as the Union
    Government, and the University Grants Commission carefully consider this problem
    and assist the teachers by requiring the payment to them of proper scales of pay and
    by insisting on the fixation of other reasonable terms and conditions of service in
    regard to teachers engaged in primary and secondary education and collegiate
    education which fall under their respective jurisdictions. The position nevertheless is
    clear that any problems connected with teachers and their salaries are outside the
    purview of the Act, and since the teachers form the sole class of employees with
    whose co-operation education is imparted by educational institutions, their exclusion
    from the purview of the Act necessarily corroborates the conclusion that education
    itself is not without its scope.
  76. Another reason has also been adduced to reinforce this conclusion:
    It is well-known that the University of Delhi and most other educational
    institutions are not formed or conducted for making profit; no doubt, the absence of
    profit motive would not take the work of any institution outside Section 2(j) if the
    65
    requirements of the said definition are otherwise satisfied. We have referred to the
    absence of profit motive only to emphasise the fact that the work undertaken by such
    educational institutions differs from the normal concept of trade or business. Indeed,
    from a rational point of view, it would be regarded as inappropriate to describe
    education even as a profession. Education in its true aspect is more a mission and a
    vocation rather than a profession or trade or business, however wide may be the
    denotation of the two latter words under the Act. That is why we think it would be
    unreasonable to hold that educational institutions are employers within the meaning
    of Section 2(g), or that the work of teaching carried on by them is an industry under
    Section 2(j), because essentially, the creation of a well-educated healthy young
    generation imbued with a rational progressive outlook on life which is the sole aim of
    education, cannot at all be compared or assimilated with what may be described as an
    industrial process.
  77. The Court was confronted by the Corporation of Nagpur where it had been
    expressly held that the education department of the Corporation was service rendered by the
    department and so the subordinate menial employees of the department came under the
    definition of employees and would be entitled to the benefits of the Act. This was explained
    away by the suggestion that
    (T)he question as to whether educational work carried on by educational institutions
    like the University of Delhi which have been formed primarily and solely for the
    purpose of imparting education amounts to an industry within the meaning of Section
    2(j), was not argued before the Court and was not really raised in that form.
  78. We dissent, with utmost deference, from these propositions and are inclined to hold,
    as the Corporation of Nagpur held, that education is industry, and as Isaacs, J. held, in the
    Australian case, that education is pre-eminently service.
  79. The actual decision in University of Delhi was supported by another ground,
    namely, that the predominant activity of the University was teaching and since teachers did
    not come within the purview of the Act, only the incidental activity of the subordinate staff
    could fall within its scope but that could not alter the predominant character of the institution.
  80. We may deal with these contentions in a brief way, since the substantial grounds on
    which we reject the reasoning have already been set out elaborately. The premises relied on is
    that the bulk of the employees in the University is the teaching community. Teachers are not
    workmen and cannot raise disputes under the Act. The subordinate staff being only a minor
    category of insignificant numbers, the institution must be excluded, going by the predominant
    character test. It is one thing to say that an institution is not an industry. It is altogether
    another thing to say that a large number of its employees are not ‘workmen’ and cannot
    therefore avail of the benefits of the Act and so the institution ceases to be an industry. The
    test is not the predominant number of employees entitled to enjoy the benefits of the Act. The
    true test is the predominant nature of the activity. In the case of the university or an
    educational institution, the nature of the activity is, ex hypothesi, education which is a service
    to the community. Ergo, the university is an industry. The error has crept in, if we may say so
    66
    with great respect, in mixing up the numerical strength of the personnel with the nature of the
    activity.
  81. Secondly, there are a number of other activities of the University Administration,
    demonstrably industrial which are severable although ancillary to the main cultural enterprise.
    For instance, a university may have a large printing press as a separate but considerable
    establishment. It may have a large fleet of transport buses with an army of running staff. It
    may have a tremendous administrative strength of officers and clerical cadres. It may have
    karamcharis of various hues. As the Corporation of Nagpur has effectively ruled, these
    operations, viewed in severally or collectively, may be treated as industry. It would be
    strange, indeed, if a university has 50 transport buses, hiring drivers, conductors, cleaners and
    workshop technicians. How are they to be denied the benefits of the Act, especially when
    their work is separable from academic teaching, merely because the buses are owned by the
    same corporate personality? We find, with all defence, little force in this process of
    nullification of the industrial character of the University’s multi-form operations.
  82. The next argument which has appealed to the Court in that case is that education
    develops the personality of the pupil and this process, if described as industry, sounds
    grotesque. We are unable to appreciate the force of this reasoning, if we may respectfully say
    so. It is true that our societal values assign a high place of honour to education, but how does
    it follow from this that education is not a service? The sequitur is not easily discernible. The
    pejorative assumption seems to be that ‘industry’ is something vulgar, inferior. disparaging
    and should not be allowed to sully the sanctified subject of education. In our view, industry is
    a noble term and embraces even the most sublime activity. At any rate, in legal terminology
    located in the statutory definition it is not money-making, it is not lucre-loving, it is not
    commercialising, it is not profit hunger. On the other hand, a team of painters who produce
    works of art and sell them or an orchestra group which travels and performs and makes
    money may be an industry if they employ supportive staff of artistes or others. There is no
    degrading touch about ‘industry’, especially in the light of Mahatma Gandhi’s dictum that
    ‘Work is Worship’. Indeed the colonial system of education, which divorced book learning
    from manual work and practical training, has been responsible for the calamities in that field.
    For that very reason, Gandhiji and Dr Zakir Hussain propagated basic education which used
    work as modus operandus for teaching. We have hardly any hesitation in regarding education
    as an industry.
  83. The final ground accepted by the Court is that education is a mission and vocation,
    rather than a profession or trade or business. The most that one can say is that this is an
    assertion which does not prove itself. Indeed, all life is a mission and a man without a mission
    is spiritually still-born. The high mission of life is the manifestation of the divinity already in
    man. To christen education as a mission, even if true, is not to negate its being an industry.
    We have to look at educational activity from the angle of the Act, and so viewed the
    ingredients of education are fulfilled. Education is, therefore, an industry and nothing can
    stand in the way of that conclusion.
  84. It may well be said by realists in the cultural field that educational managements
    depend so much on governmental support and some of them charge such high fees that
    schools have become trade and managers merchants. Whether this will apply to universities or
    67
    not, schools and colleges have been accused, at least in the private sector, of being tarnished
    with trade motives.
  85. Let us trade romantics for realities and see. With evening classes, correspondence
    courses, admissions unlimited, fees and government grants escalating, and certificates and
    degrees for prices, education – legal, medical, technological, school level or collegiateeducation – is riskless trade for cultural entrepreneurs and hapless nests of campus (industrial)
    unrest. Imaginary assumptions are experiments with untruth.
  86. Our conclusion is that the University of Delhi case was wrongly decided and that
    education can be and is, in its institutional form, an industry.
    Are charitable institutions industries?
  87. Can charity be ‘industry’? This paradox can be unlocked only by examining the
    nature of the activity of the charity, for there are charities and charities. The grammar of
    labour law in a pluralist society tells us that the worker is concerned with wages and
    conditions of service, the employer with output and economies and the community with
    peace, production and stream of supply. This complex of work, wealth and happiness, firmly
    grasped, will dissolve the dilemma of the law bearing on charitable enterprises. Charity is
    free: industry is business. Then how? A lay look may scare; a legal look will see; a social look
    will see through a hiatus inevitable in a sophisticated society with organizational diversity and
    motivational dexterity.
    125-A. If we mull over the major decisions, we get a hang of the basic structure of
    ‘industry’ in its legal anatomy. Bedrocked on the grundnorms, we must analyse the elements
    of charitable economic enterprises, established and maintained for satisfying human wants.
    Easily, three broad categories emerge; more may exist. The charitable element enlivens the
    operations at different levels in these patterns and the legal consequences are different,
    viewed from the angle of ‘industry’. For income-tax purposes, Trusts Act or company law or
    registration law or penal code requirements the examination will be different. We are
    concerned with a benignant disposition towards workmen and a trichotomy of charitable
    enterprises run for producing and/or supplying goods and services, organized systematically
    and employing workmen, is scientific.
  88. The first is one where the enterprise, like any other, yields profits but they are
    siphoned off for altruistic objects. The second is one where the institution makes no profit but
    hires the services of employees as in other like businesses but the goods and services, which
    are the output, are made available, at low or no cost, to the indigent needy who are priced out
    of the market. The third is where the establishment is oriented on a humane mission fulfilled
    by men who work, not because they are paid wages, but because they share the passion for the
    cause and derive job satisfaction from their contribution. The first two are industries, the third
    not. What is the test of identity whereby these institutions with eleemosynary inspiration fall
    or do not fall under the definition of industry?
  89. All industries are organized, systematic activity. Charitable adventures which do not
    possess this feature, of course, are not industries. Sporadic or fugitive strokes of charity do
    not become industries. All three philanthropic entities, we have itemised, fall for
    consideration only if they involve co-operation between employers and employees to produce
    68
    and/or supply goods and/or services. We assume, all three do. The crucial difference is over
    the presence of charity in the quasi-business nature of the activity. Shri Tarkunde, based on
    Safdarjung, submits that, ex hypothesi, charity frustrates commerciality and thereby deprives
    it of the character of industry.
  90. It is common ground that the first category of charities is disqualified for exemption.
    If a business is run for production and or supply of goods and services with an eye on profit, it
    is plainly an industry. The fact that the whole or substantial part of the profits so earned is
    diverted for purely charitable purposes does not affect the nature of the economic activity
    which involves the co-operation of employer and employee and results in the production of
    goods and services. The workers are not concerned about the destination of the profits. They
    work and receive wages. They are treated like any other workmen in any like industry. All the
    features of an industry, as spelt out from the definition by the decisions of this Court, are fully
    present in these charitable businesses. In short, they are industries. The application of the
    income for philanthropic purposes, instead of filling private coffers, makes no difference
    either to the employees or to the character of the activities. Good Samaritans can be clever
    industrialists.
  91. The second species of charity is really an allotropic modification of the first. If a
    kind-hearted businessman or high-minded industrialist or service-minded operator hires
    employees like his non-philanthropic counterparts and, in co-operation with them, produces
    and supplies goods or services to the lowly and the lost, the needy and the ailing without
    charging them any price or receiving a negligible return, people regard him as of charitable
    disposition and his enterprise as a charity. But then, so far as the workmen are concerned, it
    boots little whether he makes available the products free to the poor. They contribute labour
    in return for wages and conditions of service. For them the charitable employer is exactly like
    a commercial-minded employer. Both exact hardwork, both pay similar wages, both treat
    them as human machine cogs and nothing more. The material difference between the
    commercial and the compassionate employers is not with reference to the workmen but with
    reference to the recipients of goods and services. Charity operates not vis-a-vis the workmen
    in which case they will be paying a liberal wage and generous extras with no prospect of
    strike. The beneficiaries of the employer’s charity are the indigent consumers. Industrial law
    does not take note of such extraneous factors but regulates industrial relations between
    employers and employers, employers and workmen and workmen and workmen. From the
    point of view of the workmen there is no charity. For him charity must begin at home. From
    these strands of thought flows the conclusion that the second group may legitimately and
    legally be described as industry. The fallacy in the contrary contention lies in shifting the
    focus from the worker and the industrial activity to the disposal of the end product. This law
    has nothing to do with that. The income-tax law may have, social opinion may have.
  92. Some of the appellants may fall under the second category just described. While we
    are not investigating into the merits of those appeals, we may as well indicate, in a general
    way, that the Gandhi Ashram, which employs workers like spinners and weavers and supplies
    cloth or other handicraft at concessional rates to needy rural consumers, may not qualify for
    exemption. Even so, particular incidents may have to be closely probed before pronouncing
    with precision upon the nature of the activity. If cotton or yarn is given free to workers, if
    69
    charkhas are made available free for families, if fair price is paid for the net product and
    substantial charity thus benefits the spinners, weavers and other handicraftmen, one may have
    to look closely into the character of the enterprise. If employees are hired and their services
    are rewarded by wages – whether on cottage industry or factory basis – the enterprises become
    industries, even if some kind of concession is shown and even if the motive and project may
    be to encourage and help poor families and find them employment. A compassionate
    industrialist is nevertheless an industrialist. However, if raw material is made available free
    and the finished product is fully paid for – rather exceptional to imagine – the conclusion may
    be hesitant but for the fact that the integrated administrative, purchase, marketing, advertising
    and other functions are like in trade and business. This makes them industries. Noble
    objectives, pious purposes, spiritual foundations and developmental projects are no reason not
    to implicate these institutions as industries.
  93. We now move on to economic activities and occupations of an altruistic character
    falling under the third category.
  94. The heart of trade or business or analogous activity is organisation with an eye on
    competitive efficiency, by hiring employees, systematising processes, producing goods and
    services needed by the community and obtaining money’s worth of work from employees. If
    such be the nature of operations and employer-employee relations which make an enterprise
    an industry, the motivation of the employer in the final disposal of products or profits is
    immaterial. Indeed the activity is patterned on a commercial basis, judged by what other
    similar undertakings and commercial adventures do. To qualify for exemption from the
    definition of ‘industry’ in a case where there are employers and employees and systematic
    activities and production of goods and services, we need a totally different orientation,
    organisation and method which will stamp on the enterprise the imprint of commerciality.
    Special emphasis, in such cases, must be placed on the central fact of employer-employee
    relations. If a philanthropic devotion is the basis for the charitable foundation or
    establishment, the institution is headed by one who whole-heartedly dedicates himself for the
    mission and pursues it with passion, attracts others into the institution, not for wages but for
    sharing in the cause and its fulfilment, then the undertaking is not ‘industrial’. Not that the
    presence of charitable impulse extricates the institution from the definition in Section 2(j) but
    that there is no economic relationship such as is found in trade or business between the head
    who employs and the others who emotively flock to render service. In one sense, there are no
    employers and employees but crusaders all. In another sense, there is no wage basis for the
    employment but voluntary participation in the production, inspired by lofty ideals and
    unmindful of remuneration, service conditions and the like. Supposing there is an Ashram or
    Order with a guru or other head. Let us further assume that there is a band of disciples,
    devotees or priestly subordinates in the Order, gathered together for prayers, ascetic practices,
    bhajans, meditation and worship. Supposing, further, that outsiders are also invited daily or
    occasionally, to share in the spiritual proceedings. And, let us assume that all the inmates of
    the Ashram and members of the Order, invitees, guests and other outside participants are fed,
    accommodated and looked after by the institution. In such a case, as often happens, the
    cooking and the cleaning, the bed-making and service, may often be done, at least
    substantially by the Ashramites themselves. They may chant in spiritual ecstasy even as
    70
    material goods and services are made and served. They may affectionately look after the
    guests, and, all this they may do, not for wages but for the chance to propitiate the Master,
    work selflessly and acquire spiritual grace. It may well be that they may have surrendered
    their lucrative employment to come into the holy institution. It may also be that they take
    some small pocket money from the donations or takings of the institution. Nay more; there
    may be a few scavengers and servants, a part-time auditor or accountant employed on wages.
    If the substantial number of participants in making available goods and services, if the
    substantive nature of the work, as distinguished from trivial items, is rendered by voluntary
    wage-less sishyas, it is impossible to designate the institution as an industry, notwithstanding
    a marginal few who are employed on a regular basis for hire. The reason is that in the crucial,
    substantial and substantive aspects of institutional life the nature of the relations between the
    participants is non-industrial. Perhaps, when Mahatma Gandhi lived in Sabarmati, Aurobindo
    had his hallowed silence in Pondicherry, the inmates belonged to this chastened brand. Even
    now, in many foundations, centres, monasteries, holy orders and Ashrams in the East and in
    the West, spiritual fascination pulls men and women into the precincts and they work
    tirelessly for the Maharishi or Yogi or Swamiji and are not wage-earners in any sense of the
    term. Such people are not workmen and such institutions are not industries despite some
    menials and some professionals in a vast complex being hired. We must look at the
    predominant character of the institution and the nature of the relations resulting in the
    production of goods and services. Stray wage-earning employees do not shape the soul of an
    institution into an industry.
    Research
  95. Does research involve collaboration between employer and employee ? It does. The
    employer is the institution, the employees are the scientists, para-scientists and other
    personnel. Is scientific research service? Undoubtedly it is. Its discoveries are valuable
    contributions to the wealth of the nation. Such discoveries may be sold for a heavy price in
    the industrial or other markets. Technology has to be paid for and technological inventions
    and innovations may be patented and sold. In our scientific and technological age nothing has
    more cash value, as intangible goods and invaluable services, than discoveries. For instance,
    the discoveries of Thomas Alva Edison made from fabulously rich. It has been said that his
    brain had the highest cash value in history for he made the world vibrate with the miraculous
    discovery of recorded sound. Unlike most inventors, he did not have to wail to get his reward
    in heaven; he received it munificently on this gratified and grateful earth, thanks to
    conversion of his inventions into money aplenty. Research benefits industry. Even though a
    research institute may be a separate entity disconnected from the many industries which
    funded the institute itself, it can be regarded as an organisation, propelled by systematic
    activity, modelled on co-operation between employer and employee and calculated to throw
    up discoveries and inventions and useful solutions which benefit individual industries and the
    nation in terms of goods and services and wealth. It follows that research institutes, albeit run
    without profit-motive, are industries.
    Clubs
  96. Are clubs industries? The wide words used in Section 2(j) if applied without rational
    limitations, may cover every bilateral activity even spiritual, religious, domestic, conjugal,
    71
    pleasurable or political. But functional circumscriptions spring from the subject-matter and
    other cognate considerations already set out early in this judgment. Industrial law, any law,
    may insanely run amok if limitless lexical liberality were to innate expressions into bursting
    point or proliferate odd judicial arrows which at random sent, hit many an irrelevant mark the
    legislative archer never meant. To read down words to yield relevant sense is a pragmatic art,
    if care is taken to eschew subjective projections masked as judicial processes. The true test, as
    we apprehend from the economic history and functional philosophy of the Act is based on the
    pathology of industrial friction and explosion impeding community production and
    consumption and imperilling peace and welfare. This social pathology arises from the
    exploitative potential latent in organized employer-employee relations. So, where the
    dichotomy of employer and workmen in the process of material production is present, the
    service of economic friction and need for conflict resolution show up. The Act is meant to
    obviate such confrontation and ‘industry’ cannot functionally and defunctionally exceed this
    object. The question is whether in a club situation – or of a co-operative or even a monastery
    situation, for that matter – a dispute potential of the nature suggested exists. If it does, it is an
    industry, since the basic elements are satisfied If productive co-operation between employer
    and employee is necessary, conflict between them is on the cards, be it a social club, mutual
    benefit society, panjarapole, public service or professional office. Tested on this touchstone,
    most clubs will fail to qualify for exemption. For clubs – gentlemen’s clubs, proprietory clubs,
    service clubs, investment clubs, sports clubs, art clubs, military clubs or other brands of
    recreational associations – when X-rayed from the industrial angle, project a picture on the
    screen typical of employers hiring employees for wages for rendering services and/or
    supplying goods on a systematic basis at specified hours. There is a co-operation, the club
    management providing the capital, the raw material, the appliances and auxiliaries and the
    cooks, waiters, bell boys, pickers, barmaids or other servants making available enjoyable eats,
    pleasures and other permissible services for price paid by way of subscriptions or bills
    charged. The club life, the warm company, the enrichment of the spirits and freshening of the
    mind are there. But these blessings do not contradict the co-existence of an ‘industry’ in the
    technical sense. Even tea-tasters, hired for high wages, or commercial art troupes or games
    teams remunerated fantastically, enjoy company, taste, travel and games; but, elementally,
    they are workmen with employers above and together constitute not merely entertainment
    groups but industries under the Act. The protean hues of human organization project
    delightfully different designs depending upon the legal prism and the filtering process used.
    No one can deny the cultural value of club life; neither can anyone blink at the legal result of
    the organization.
  97. The only ground to extricate clubs from the coils of industrial law (except specific
    statutory provision) is absence of employer-employee co-operation on the familiar luringfiring pattern. Before we explain this possible exemption and it applies to many clubs at the
    poorer levels of society we must meet another submission made by Counsel. Clubs are
    exclusive; they cater to needs and pleasures of members, not of the community as such and
    this latter feature salvages them from the clutches of industrial regulation. We do not agree.
    Clubs are open to the public for membership subject to their own bye-laws and rules. But any
    member of the community complying with those conditions and waiting for his turn has a
    reasonable chance of membership. Even the world’s summit club – the United Nations has
    72
    cosmic membership subject to vetoes, qualifications, voting and what not. What we mean is
    that a club is not a limited partnership but formed from the community. Moreover, even the
    most exclusive clubs of imperial vintage and class snobbery admit members’ guests who are
    not specific souls but come from the undefused community or part of a community. Clubs,
    speaking generally are social institutions enlivening community life and are the fresh breath
    of relaxation in a faded society. They serve a section and answer the doubtful test of serving
    the community. They are industry.
  98. Even these people’s organs cannot be non-industries unless one strict condition is
    fulfilled. They should be – and usually are – self-serving. They are poor men’s clubs without
    the wherewithal of a Gymkhana or Cricket Club of India which reached this Court for
    adjudication. Indeed, they rarely reach a Court being easily priced out of our expensive
    judicial market. These self-service clubs do not have hired employees to cook or serve, to
    pick or chase balls, to tie up nets or arrange the cards table, the billiards table, the bar and the
    bath or do those elaborate business management chores of the well-run city or country clubs.
    The members come and arrange things for themselves. The secretary, an elected member,
    keeps the key. Those interested in particular pursuits organize those terms themselves. Even
    the small accounts or clerical items are maintained by one member or other. On special
    evenings all contribute efforts to make a good show, excursion, joy picnic or anniversary
    celebration. The dynamic aspect is self-service. In such an institution, a part-time sweeper or
    scanvenger or multi-purpose attendant may sometimes exist. He may be an employee. This
    marginal element does not transform a little association into an industry. We have projected
    an imprecise profile and there may be minor variations. The central thrust of our proposition
    is that if a club or other like collectivity has a basic and dominant self-service mechanism, a
    modicum of employees at the periphery will not metamorphose it into a conventional club
    whose verve and virtue are taken care of by paid staff, and the members’ role is to enjoy. The
    small man’s Nehru Club, Gandhi Granthasala, Anna Manram, Netaji Youth Centre, Brother
    Music Club, Muslim Sports Club and like organs often named after national or provincial
    heroes and manned by members themselves as contrasted with the upper bracket’s Gymkhana
    Club, Cosmopolitan Club, Cricket Club of India, National Sports Club of India whose badge
    is pleasure paid for and provided through skilled or semi-skilled catering staff. We do not deal
    with hundred per cent social service clubs which meet once in a way, hire a whole evening in
    some hotel, have no regular staff and devote their energies and resources also to social service
    projects. There are many brands and we need not deal with every one. Only if they answer the
    test laid down affirmatively they qualify.
  99. The Madras Gymkhana Club, a blue-blooded members’ club, has the socialite
    cream of the city on its rolls. It offers choice facilities for golf, tennis and billiards, arranges
    dances, dinners and refreshments, entertains and accommodates guests and conducts
    tournaments for members and non-members. These are all activities richly charged with
    pleasurable service. For fulfilment of these objects the club employs officers, caterers, and
    others on reasonable salaries. Does this club become an industry? The label matters little; the
    substance is the thing. A night-club for priced nocturnal sex is a lascivious ‘industry’. But a
    literary club, meeting weekly to read or discuss poetry, hiring a venue and running solely by
    the self-help of the participants, is not. Hidayatullah, C.J., in Gymkhana ruled that the club
    73
    was not an ‘industry’. Reason? ‘An industry is thus said to involve co-operation between
    employer and employees for the object of satisfying material human needs but not for oneself
    nor for pleasure nor necessarily for profit’.
    It is not of any consequence that there is no profit motive because that is
    considered immaterial. It is also true that the affairs of the club are organised in the
    way business is organised, and that there is production of material and other services
    and in a limited way production of material goods mainly in the catering department.
    But these circumstances are not truly representative in the case of the club because
    the services are to the members themselves for their own pleasure and amusement
    and the material goods are for their consumption. In other words, the club exists for
    its members. No doubt occasionally strangers also take benefit from its services but
    they can only do so on invitation of members. No one outside the list of members has
    the advantage of these services as of right. Nor can these privileges be bought. In fact
    they are available only to members or through members.
    If today the club were to stop entry of outsiders, no essential change in its
    character vis-a-vis the members would take place. In other words, the circumstances
    that guests are admitted is irrelevant to determine if the club is an industry. Even with
    the admission of guests being open the club remains the same, that is to say, a
    member’s self-serving institution. No doubt the material needs or wants of a section
    of the community is catered for but that is not enough. This must be done as part of
    trade or business or as an undertaking analogous to trade or business. This element is
    completely missing in a members’ club.
  100. Why is the club not an industry? It involves co-operation of employer and
    employees, organised like in a trade and calculated to supply pleasurable utilities to members
    and others. The learned Judge agrees that “the material needs or wants of a section of the
    community is catered for but that is not enough. This must be done as part of trade or business
    or as an undertaking analogous to trade or business. This element is completely missing in a
    members’ club”.
  101. ‘This element’? What element makes it analogous to trade? Profit motive? No, says
    the learned Judge. Because it is a self-serving institution? Yes? Not at all. For, if it is selfservice then why the expensive establishment and staff with high salary bills? It is plain as
    day-light that the club members do nothing to produce the goods or services. They are
    rendered by employees who work for wages. The members merely enjoy club life, the
    geniality of company and exhilarating camaraderie, to the accompaniment of dinners, dances,
    games and thrills. The ‘reason’ one may discover is that it is a members’ club in the sense that
    “the club belongs to members for the time being on its list of members and that is what
    matters. Those members can deal with the club as they like. Therefore, the club is identified
    with its members at a given point of time. Thus it cannot be said that the club has an existence
    apart from the members”.
  102. We are intrigued by this reason. The ingredients necessary for an industry are
    present here and yet it is declared a non-industry because the club belongs to members only.
    A company belongs to the shareholders only; a co-operative belongs to the members only; a
    74
    firm of experts belongs to the partners only. And yet, if they employ workmen with whose cooperation goods and services are made available to a section of the community and the
    operations are organised in the manner typical of business method and organisation, the
    conclusion is irresistible that an ‘industry’ emerges. Likewise, the members of a club may
    own the institution and become the employers for that reason. It is transcendental logic to
    jettison the inference of an ‘industry’ from such a factual situation on the ingenious plea that a
    club “belongs to members for the time being and that is what matters”. We are inclined to
    think that that just does not matter. The Gymkhana case, we respectfully. hold, is wrongly
    decided.
  103. The Cricket Club of India stands in a worse position. It is a huge undertaking with
    activities wide-ranging, with big budgets, army of staff and profit-making adventures. Indeed,
    the members share in the gains of these adventures by getting money’s worth by cheaper
    accommodation, free or low priced tickets for entertainment and concessional refreshments;
    and yet Bhargava, J. speaking for the Court held this mammoth industry a non-industry.
    Why? Is the promotion of sports and games by itself a legal reason for excluding the
    organisation from the category of industries if all the necessary ingredients are present? Is the
    fact that the residential facility is exclusive for members an exemptive factor? Do not the
    members share in the profits through the invisible process of lower charges? When all these
    services are rendered by hired employees, how can the nature of the activity be described as
    self-service, without taking liberty with reality? A number of utilities which have money’s
    worth, are derived by the members. An indefinite section of the community entering as the
    guests of the members also share in these services. The testimony of the activities can leave
    none in doubt that this colossal ‘club’ is a vibrant collective undertaking which offers goods
    and services to a section of the community for payment and there is co-operation between
    employer and employees in this project. The plea of non-industry is un-presentable and
    exclusion is possible only by straining law to snapping point to salvage a certain class of
    socialite establishments. Presbyter is only priest writ large. Club is industry manu brevi.
    Co-operatives
    Co-operative societies ordinarily cannot, we feel, fall outside Section 2(j). After all, the
    society, a legal person, is the employer. The members and/or others are employees and the
    activity partakes of the nature of trade. Merely because co-operative enterprises deserve State
    encouragement the definition cannot be distorted. Even if the society is worked by the
    members only, the entity (save where they are few and self-serving) is an industry because the
    member-workers are paid wages and there can be disputes about rates and different scales of
    wages among the categories i.e. workers and workers or between workers and employer.
    These societies – credit societies, marketing co-operatives, producers’ or consumers’ societies
    or apex societies – are industries.
  104. Do credit unions, organised on a co-operative basis, scale the definitional walls of
    industry? They do. There, a credit union, which was a co-operative association which pooled
    the savings of small people and made loans to its members at low interest, was considered
    from the point of view of industry. Admittedly, they were credit unions incorporated as cooperative societies and the thinking of Mason, J. was that such institutions were industrial in
    character. The industrial mechanism of society according to Starke, J. included “all those
    75
    bodies ‘of men associated, in various degrees of competition and co-operation, to win their
    living by providing the community with some service which it requires’ “. Mason, J., went a
    step further to hold that even if such credit unions were an adjunct of industry, they could be
    regarded as industry.
  105. It is enough, therefore, if the activities carried on by credit unions can accurately be
    described as incidental to industry or to the organized production , transportation or
    distribution of commodities or other forms of material wealth. To our minds the evidence
    admits of no doubt that the activities of credit unions are incidental in this sense.
  106. This was sufficient, in his view, to conclude that credit unions constituted an
    industry under an Act which has resemblance to our own. In our view, therefore, societies are
    industries.
    The Safdarjung Hospital case
  107. A sharp bend in the course of the law came when Safdarjung was decided. The
    present reference has come from that landmark case, and, necessarily, it claims our close
    attention. Even so, no lengthy discussion is called for, because the connotation of ‘industry’
    has already been given by us at sufficient length to demarcate our deviation from the decision
    in Safdarjung.
  108. Hidayatullah, C.J., considered the facts of the appeals, clubbed together there and
    held that all the three institutions in the bunch of appeals were not industries. Abbreviated
    reasons were given for the holding in regard to each institution, which we may extract for
    precise understanding:
    It is obvious that Safdarjung Hospital is not embarked on an economic activity
    which can be said to be analogous to trade or business. There is no evidence that it is
    more than a places where persons can get treated. This is a part of the functions of
    Government and the hospital is run as a Department of Government. It cannot,
    therefore, be said to be an industry.
    The Tuberculosis Hospital is not an independent institution. It is a part of the
    Tuberculosis Association of India. The hospital is wholly charitable and is a research
    institute. The dominant purpose of the hospital is research and training, but as
    research and training cannot be given without beds in a hospital, the hospital is run.
    Treatment is thus a part of research and training. In these circumstances the
    Tuberculosis Hospital cannot be described as industry.
    The objects of the Kurji Holy Family Hospital are entirely charitable. It carries
    on work of training, research and treatment. Its income is mostly from donations and
    distribution of surplus as profit is prohibited. It is, therefore, clear that it is not an
    industry as laid down in the Act.
  109. Even a cursory glance makes it plain that the learned Judge took the view that a
    place of treatment of patients, run as a department of government, was not an industry
    because it was a part of the functions of the government. We cannot possibly agree that
    running a hospital, which is a welfare activity and not a sovereign function, cannot be an
    industry. Likewise, dealing with the Tuberculosis Hospital case, the learned Judge held that
    76
    the hospital was wholly charitable and also was a research institute. Primarily, it was an
    institution for research and training. Therefore, the Court concluded, the institution could not
    be described as industry. Non-sequitur. Hospital facility, research products and training
    services are surely services and hence industry. It is difficult to agree that a hospital is not an
    industry. In the third case the same factors plus the prohibition of profit are relied on by the
    Court. We find it difficult to hold that absence of profit, or functions of training and research,
    take the institution out of the scope of industry.
  110. Although the facts of the three appeals considered in Safdarjung related only to
    hospitals with research and training component, the Bench went extensively into a survey of
    the earlier precedents and crystallisation of criteria for designating industries. After stating
    that trade and business have a wide connotation, Hidayatullah, C.J., took the view that
    professions must be excluded from the ambit of industry: “A profession ordinarily is an
    occupation requiring intellectual skill, often coupled with manual skill. Thus a teacher uses
    purely intellectual skill, while a painter uses both. In any event, they are not engaged in an
    occupation in which employers and employees co-operate in the production or sale of
    commodities or arrangement for their production or sale or distribution and their services
    cannot be described as material services”.
  111. We are unable to agree with this rationale. It is difficult to understand why a school
    or a painting institute or a studio which uses the services of employees and renders the service
    to the community cannot be regarded as an industry. What is more baffling is the subsequent
    string of reasons presented by the learned Judge:
    What is meant by “material services” needs some explanation too. Material
    services are not services which depend wholly or largely upon the contribution of
    professional knowledge, skill or dexterity for the production of a result. Such services
    being given individually and by individuals are services no doubt but not material
    services. Even an establishment where many such operate cannot be said to convert
    their professional services into material services. Material services involve an activity
    carried on through co-operation between employers and employees to provide the
    community with the use of something such as electric power, water, transportation,
    mail delivery, telephones and the like. In providing these services there may be
    employment of trained men and even professional men, but the emphasis is not on
    what these men do but upon the productivity of a service organised as an industry and
    commercially valuable. Thus the services of professional men involving benefit to
    individuals according to their needs, such as doctors, teachers, lawyers, solicitors etc.,
    are easily distinguishable from an activity such as transport service. The latter is of a
    commercial character in which something is brought into existence quite apart from
    the benefit to particular individuals. It is the production of this something which is
    described as the production of material services.
  112. With the greatest respect to the learned Chief Justice, the arguments strung together
    in this paragraph are too numerous and subtle for us to imbibe. It is transcendental to define
    material services as excluding professional services. We have explained this position at some
    length elsewhere in this judgment and do not feel the need to repeat. Nor are we convinced
    that Gymkhana and Cricket Club of India are correctly decided. The learned Judge placed
    77
    accent on the non-profit making members’ club as being outside the pale of trade or industry.
    We demur to this proposition.
  113. Another intriguing reasoning in the judgment is that the Court has stated “it is not
    necessary that there must be a profit motive but the enterprises must be analogous to trade or
    business in a commercial sense”. However, somewhat contrary to this reasoning we find, in
    the concluding part of the judgment, emphasis on the non-profit making aspect of the
    institutions. Equally puzzling is the reference to “commercial sense”: what precisely does this
    expression mean? It is interesting to note that the word “commercial” has more than one
    semantic shade. If it means profit-making, the reasoning is self-contradictory. If it merely
    means a commercial pattern of organisation, of hiring and firing employees, of indicating the
    nature of employer-employee relation as in trade or commercial house, then the activityoriented approach is the correct one. On that footing, the conclusions reached in that case do
    not follow. As a matter of fact, Hidayatullah, C.J., had in Gymkhana turned down the test of
    commerciality: “Trade is only one aspect of industrial activity …. This requires co-operation
    in some form between employers and workmen and the result is directly the product of this
    association but not necessarily commercial”. Indeed, while dealing with the reasoning in
    Hospital Mazdoor Sabha he observes: “if a hospital, nursing home or a dispensary is run as a
    business, in a commercial way, there may be found elements of an industry there”. This facet
    suggests either profit motive, which has been expressly negatived in the very case, or
    commercial-type of activity, regardless of profit, which affirms the test which we have
    accepted, namely, that there must be employer-employee relations more or less on the pattern
    of trade or business. All that we can say is that there are different strands of reasoning in the
    judgment which are somewhat difficult to reconcile. Of course, when the learned Judge states
    that the use of the first schedule to the Act depends on the condition precedent of the
    existence of an industry, we agree. But, that by itself does not mean that a hospital cannot be
    regarded as an industry, profit or no profit, research or no research. We have adduced enough
    reasons in the various portions of this judgment to regard hospitals, research institutions and
    training centres as valuable material services to the community, qualifying for coming within
    Section 2(j). We must plainly state that vis-a-vis hospitals, Safdarjung was wrong and
    Hospital Mazdoor Sabha was right.
  114. Because of the problems of reconciliation of apparently contradictory strands of
    reasoning in Safdarjung we find subsequent cases of this Court striking different notes. In
    fact, one of us (Bhagwati, J.) in Indian Standards Institution referred, even at the opening, to
    the baffling, perplexing question which judicial ventures had not solved. We fully endorse the
    observations of the Court in ISI:
    So infinitely varied and many-sided is human activity and with the incredible
    growth and progress in all branches of knowledge and ever widening areas of
    experience at all levels, it is becoming so diversified and expanding in so many
    directions hitherto unthought of, that no rigid and doctrinaire approach can be
    adopted in considering this question. Such an approach would fail to measure up to
    the needs of the growing welfare state which is constantly engaged in undertaking
    new and varied activities as part of its social welfare policy. The concept of industry,
    which is intended to be a convenient and effective tool in the hands of industrial
    78
    adjudication for bringing about industrial peace and harmony, would lose its capacity
    for adjustment and change. It would be petrified and robbed of its dynamic content.
    The Court should, therefore, so far as possible, avoid formulating or adopting
    generalisations and hesitate to cast the concept of industry in a narrow rigid mould
    which would not permit of expansion as and when necessity arises. Only some
    working principles may be evolved which would furnish guidance in determining
    what are the attributes or characteristics which would ordinarily indicate that an
    undertaking is analogous to trade or business.
  115. Our endeavour in this decision is to provide such working principles. This Court,
    within a few years of the enactment of the salutary statute, explained the benign sweep of
    ‘industry’ in Banerji which served as beacon in later years – Ahmedabad Textile Research
    acted on it, Hospital Mazdoor Sabha and Nagpur Corporation marched in its sheen. The law
    shed steady light on industrial inter-relations and the country’s tribunals and courts settled
    down to evolve a progressive labour jurisprudence, burying the bad memories of laissez faire
    and bitter struggles in this field and nourishing new sprouts of legality fertilised by the
    seminal ratio in Banerji. Indeed, every great judgment is not merely an adjudication of an
    existing lis but an appeal addressed by the present to the emerging future. And here the future
    responded, harmonising with the human-scape hopefully projected by Part IV of the
    Constitution. But the drama of a nation’s life, especially when it confronts die-hard forces,
    develops situations of imbroglio and tendencies to back-track. And law quibbles where life
    wobbles. Judges only read signs and translate symbols in the national sky. So, ensued an era
    of islands of exception dredged up by judicial process. Great clubs were privileged out, liberal
    professions swam to safety, educational institutions, vast and small, were helped out, divers
    charities, disinclined to be charitable to their own weaker workmen, made pious pleas and
    philanthropic appeals to be extricated. A procession of decisions – Solicitors’ case, University
    of Delhi, Gymkhana Club, Cricket Club of India. Chartered Accountants climaxed by
    Safdarjung, – carved out sanctuaries. The six-member Bench, the largest which sat on this
    Court conceptually to reconstruct ‘industry’, affirmed and reversed, held profit motive
    irrelevant but upheld charitable service as exemptive, and in its lights and shadows, judicial
    thinking became ambivalent and industrial jurisprudence landed itself in a legal quagmire.
    Pinjrapoles sought salvation and succeeded in principle (Bombay Panjrapole), Chambers of
    Commerce fought and failed, hospitals battled to victory [Dhanrajgirji Hospital], standards
    institute made a vain bid to extricate [ISI case], research institutes, at the High Court level,
    waged and won non-industry status in Madras and Kerala. The murky legal sky paralysed
    tribunals and courts and administrations, and then came, in consequence, this reference to a
    larger Bench of seven Judges.
  116. Banerji, amplified by Corporation of Nagpur, in effect met with its Waterloo in
    Safdarjung. But in this latter case two voices could be heard and subsequent rulings
    zigzagged and conflicted precisely because of this built-in ambivalence. It behoves us,
    therefore, hopefully to abolish blurred edges, illumine penumbral areas and overrule what we
    regard as wrong. Hesitancy, half-tones and hunting with the hounds and running with the hare
    can claim heavy penalty in the shape of industrial confusion, adjudicatory quandary and
    administrative perplexity at a time when the nation is striving to promote employment
    79
    through diverse strategies which need, for their smooth fulfilment, less stress and distress,
    more mutual understanding and trust based on a dynamic rule of law which speaks clearly,
    firmly and humanely. If the salt of law lose its savour of progressive certainty wherewith shall
    it be salted? So we proceed to formulate the principles, deducible from our discussion, which
    are decisive, positively and negatively, of the identity of ‘industry’ under the Act. We speak,
    not exhaustively, but to the extent covered by the debate at the bar and, to that extent,
    authoritatively, until overruled by a larger Bench or superseded by the legislative branch.
    I
    ‘Industry’, as defined in Section 2(j) and explained in Banerji (supra), has a wide import.
    (a) Where (i) systematic activity, (ii) organized by co-operation between employer
    and employee (the direct and substantial element is chimerical) (iii) for the production
    and/or distribution of goods and services calculated to satisfy human wants and wishes
    (not spiritual or religious but inclusive of material things or services geared to celestial
    bliss e.g. making, on a large scale prasad or food), prima facie, there is an ‘industry’ in
    that enterprise.
    (b) Absence of profit motive or gainful objective is irrelevant, be the venture in the
    public, joint, private or other sector.
    (c) The true focus is functional and the decisive test is the nature of the activity with
    special emphasis on the employer-employee relations.
    (d) If the organization is a trade or business it does not cease to be one because of
    philanthropy animating the undertaking.
    II
    Although Section 2(j) uses words of the widest amplitude in its two limbs, their meaning
    cannot be magnified to overreach itself.
    (a) ‘Undertaking’ must suffer a contextual and associational shrinkage as explained in
    Banerji and in this judgment; so also, service, calling and the like. This yields the
    inference that all organized activity possessing the triple elements in I (supra), although
    not trade or business, may still be ‘industry’ provided the nature of the activity, viz. the
    employer-employee basis, bears resemblance to what we find in trade or business. This
    takes into the fold of ‘industry’ undertakings, callings and services, adventures ‘analogous
    to the carrying on the trade or business’. All features, other than the methodology of
    carrying on the activity viz. in organizing the co-operation between employer and
    employee, may be dissimilar. It does not matter, if on the employment terms there is
    analogy.
    III
    Application of these guidelines should not stop short of their logical reach by invocation
    of creeds, cults or inner sense of incongruity or outer sense of motivation for or resultant of
    the economic operations. The ideology of the Act being industrial peace, regulation and
    resolution of industrial disputes between employer and workmen, the range off this statutory
    ideology must inform the reach of the statutory definition. Nothing less, nothing more.
    80
    (a) The consequences are (i) professions, (ii) clubs, (iii) educational institutions, (iv)
    co-operatives, (v) research institutes (vi) charitable projects and (vii) other kindred
    adventures, if they fulfil the triple tests listed in I (supra), cannot be exempted from the
    scope of Section 2(j).
    (b) A restricted category of professions, clubs, co-operatives and even gurukulas and
    little research labs, may qualify for exemption if, in simple ventures, substantially and,
    going by the dominant nature criterion, substantively, no employees are entertained but in
    minimal matters, marginal employees are hired without destroying the non-employee
    character of the unit.
    (c) If, in a pious or altruistic mission many employ themselves, free or for small
    honoraria or like return, mainly drawn by sharing in the purpose or cause, such as lawyers
    volunteering to run a free legal services clinic or doctors serving in their spare hours in a
    free medical centre or ashramites working at the bidding of the holiness, divinity or like
    central personality, and the services are supplied free or at nominal cost and those who
    serve are not engaged for remuneration or on the basis of master and servant relationship,
    then, the institution is not an industry even if stray servants, manual or technical, are
    hired. Such eleemosynary or like undertakings alone are exempt — not other generosity,
    compassion, developmental passion or project.
    IV
    The dominant nature test
    (a) Where a complex of activities, some of which qualify for exemption, others not,
    involves employees on the total undertaking, some of whom are not ‘workmen’ as in the
    University of Delhi case or some departments are not productive of goods and services if
    isolated, even then, the predominant nature of the services and the integrated nature of the
    departments as explained in the Corporation of Nagpur, will be the true test. The whole
    undertaking will be ‘industry’ although those who are not ‘workmen’ by definition may
    not benefit by the status.
    (b) Notwithstanding the previous clauses, sovereign functions, strictly understood,
    (alone) qualify for exemption, not the welfare activities or economic adventures
    undertaken by government or statutory bodies.
    (c) Even in departments discharging sovereign functions, if there are units which are
    industries and they are substantially severable, then they can be considered to come
    within Section 2(j).
    (d) Constitutional and competently enacted legislative provisions may well remove
    from the scope of the Act categories which otherwise may be covered thereby.
    V
    We overrule Safdarjung. Solicitors’ case, Gymkhana, Delhi University, Dhanrajgirji
    Hospital and other rulings whose ratio runs counter to the principles enunciated above, and
    Hospital Mazdoor Sabha is hereby rehabilitated.
    81
    We conclude with diffidence because Parliament, which has the commitment to the
    political nation to legislate promptly in vital areas like Industry and Trade and articulate the
    welfare expectations in the ‘conscience’ portion of the Constitution, has hardly intervened to
    re-structure the rather clumsy, vapourous and tall-and-dwarf definition or tidy up the scheme
    although judicial thesis and anti-thesis, disclosed in the two-decades-long decisions, should
    have produced a legislative synthesis becoming of a welfare state and socialistic society, in a
    world setting where I.L.O. norms are advancing and India needs updating. We feel confident,
    in another sense, since Counsel stated at the bar that a bill on the subject is in the offing. The
    rule of law, we are sure, will run with the rule of life – Indian life – at the threshold of the
    decade of new development in which labour and management, guided by the State, will
    constructively partner the better production and fair diffusion of national wealth. We have
    stated that, save the Bangalore Water Supply and Sewerage Board appeal, we are not
    disposing of the others on the merits. We dismiss that appeal with costs and direct that all the
    others be posted before a smaller Bench for disposal on the merits in accordance with the
    principles of law herein laid down.

Related posts

Afcons Infrastructure Ltd. v. Cherian VarkeyConstruction Company Pvt. Ltd.(2010) 8 SCC 24

vikash Kumar

Abdul Hafiz Beg v. SahebbiAIR 1975 Bom. 165

vikash Kumar

Uttam v. Saubhag Singh(2016) 4 SCC 68

Tabassum Jahan

Leave a Comment